CO ». [I LIL. PHYSICAL EEALISM 1'IUNTKD BY SrOTTLSWOODE AND CO., NEW-STUEET SQUAUB LONDON PHYSICAL REALISM J5KING AN ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY FROM THE PHYSICAL OBJECTS OF SCIENCE TO THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE BY THOMAS CASE, M.A. AXU SENIOR TUTOH CORPUS CHRIST! COI.LKCJE, AND LECTUUBR AT CHKIST CHL'IICH; FOUMKHLY FEIJ.UW OK BKAHBXOSE AND TUTOIl OK BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFOKD drrodflgui A«y/£rt*caw— AKISTOTLE LONDON L 0 X G 11 A X S, GHEE X, A X I) C 0. AND NE\y YOliK : 15 EAST 10"' STKEET 1888 , All right. 3 ff*rrrr,l ' Neque tamen illis nihil adtli posse affirmamus : sed contra, nos, qui Mentem respicimus non tantuin in facultate propria, sed quatenus copulatur cum Rebus, Artem Inveniendi cum Inventis adolescere posse, statuere debemus.' BACON, Nov. Org. i. 130. TO WILLIAM S. SAYOBY, F.E.S. SURGEON -EXTRAORDINARY TO H.M. THE QUEEN PRESIDENT Of THE ROYAL COLLEGE OF SURGEONS OF ENGLAND SURGEON TO ST BARTHOLOMEW'S HOSPITAL CONTENTS. PART I. GENERAL PROOF OF PHYSICAL REALISM. CHAP. I. THE PHYSICAL OBJECT OF SCIENCE . . 3 II. IDEALISM AND REALISM . ]3 III. THE PHYSICAL DATA OP SENSE . 40 IV. THE HISTORICAL ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 82 PART 11. PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM. V. DESCARTES JQJ VI. LOCKE J41 VII. BERKELEY .... |fl(j vin. BERKELEY'S THEORY OF VISION . 225 IX. HUME Ofj(j x. KANT'S 'CRITIQUE' AND NECESSARY TRUTHS . . . .°,19 APPENDIX QQQ PART I. GENERAL PROOF OF PHYSICAL REALISM. ' Itaqiie contemplatio fere desinit cum aspcctu ; adeo ut rerum invisibilium cxigua aut nulla sit observation BACON, Nov. Org. i. 50. CHAPTEE I. THE PHYSICAL OBJECT OF SCIENCE. ' NATURAL PHILOSOPHY, as now regarded, treats generally of the physical universe, and deals fearlessly alike with quantities too great to be distinctly conceived, and with quantities almost infinitely too small to be perceived even with the most powerful microscopes ; such as, for instance, distances through which the light of stars or nebulas, though moving at the rate of about 186,000 miles per second, takes many years to travel ; or the size of the particles of water, whose number in a single drop may, as we have reason to believe, amount to somewhere about 102G, or 100,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000. Yet we successfully inquire not only into the composi tion of the atmospheres of these distant stars, but into the number and properties of these water-particles ; nay, even into the laws by which they act upon one another.' This quotation from Professor Tait's ' Recent Ad vances in Physical Science ' is a recognition of the reality of the insensible, and of its knowledge by the natural philosopher, as facts. No metaphysical theory of existence can be complete, unless it recognises the known reality of the insensible physical world ; and no psychological theory of human knowledge can be accepted as even a probable hypothesis, unless it B 2 4 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. explains how these scientific objects of human know ledge are known from the original data of sense. The distinction between the sensible and the scien tific-, the apparent and the real, the perceptible and the imperceptible, is not only a scientific fact but has be come a commonplace in natural philosophy, without having produced any marked effect in mental philo sophy. Astronomy has long opposed the real to the apparent motions of celestial bodies ; and Sir Isaac Newton carried this contrast so far as to oppose abso lute, true and mathematical, to relative, apparent and common, time and space. In physics, apparent size is the room which a body seems to occupy, physical size is the real space taken up by its particles. Not only physics, but chemistry and biology unite in the anti thesis of molar and molecular motion, in recognising therefore motions which are for the most part imper ceptible, in resolving what seem to our senses to be heterogeneous qualities into mere varieties of imper ceptible motion, and in referring these motions to particles which are as imperceptible as the motions themselves. In all these sciences the latent structures and processes of things are opposed to their external appearances and perceptible changes. I do not mean that these undeniable conclusions, very far removed as they are from the original data of observation and experiment, are at all inconsistent with the sensations, perceptions, observations, or experiences which ordinary men have, and from which the natural philosopher starts. On the contrary, the very untutored senses themselves are best explained — nay, can be only explained — by statements at first sight opposed to them. It is only in appearance that the motion of the earth round the sun contradicts our senses, for, though ciiAr. i. THE PHYSICAL OBJECT OF SCIENCE 0 it contradicts one single appearance, the whole sum of astronomical observations is only to be explained by means of it. Similarly, when it is said that one thing is apparently larger and physically smaller than another, vision is contradicted, but the sense of touch is justified, and our experience as a whole explained. The latent motions of particles, into which sensible qualities are resolved, at first sight contradict but really explain the whole system of our sensations of touch, vision, and hearing. But though the results of science thus explain the data of sense, it must be remembered that they only explain them, and are not themselves data of sense. No man can make himself see the earth going round the sun, except by standing on the sun itself. No man can see light at the moment when it starts from a distant star years before it reaches his senses. Micro scopes can be multiplied in power, but they are millions short of the actual (I do not speak of the potential) divisibility of the particles of things. Moreover, the natural philosopher gives even greater reality to the imperceptible than to the perceptible. The astronomer not only opposes but prefers real to apparent motion, the physicist physical to apparent size, and all natural philosophers latent structures and molecular processes to masses and their molar motions. It is not too much to say, that the mission of modern as well as of ancient philosophy is to convince mankind that sense is unequal to the subtlety of things ; to get behind the scenes and see the machinery of nature at work ; to recognise the insensible as real, yes, and more real, than the sensible. Sense is not science. Our knowledge is not limited to sensible pheno mena. We are quite as certain of the existence of 0 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. that which cannot be brought within our sensibility as of that which can, and of objects which we do not experience as of objects of experience itself. Further, we are quite as certain that they exist in space and in time ; for if they are not in space they have no size, if they are not in time they have no dura tion, and that which has neither any size nor any dura tion is nothing ; and, if they are neither in time nor space, they do not move, for motion is change of place in space during time. Space and time are not mere forms of our sensibility, but conditions of things and their motions beyond the range of our sensibility. We not only know that the imperceptible exists, and that it exists in space and time, but also we know im perceptible attributes both of the perceptible and of the imperceptible. For example, I know that the hour-hand of my watch moves, though I cannot perceive it moving, as well as that the minute-hand moves which I can per ceive moving with difficulty, or the second-hand which I can perceive moving with ease. I know that the im perceptible particles of matter gravitate imperceptibly towards one another, as well as I know that their masses gravitate, and that unless gravitation is true of the former, it is not true of the latter. Still more insensible are cohesion and chemical affinity, which are imper ceptible motions exerted between imperceptible particles and at imperceptible distances. The whole of modern science is based on the fact that there are numerous latent structures and latent processes which are known to be real attributes of particles themselves latent. He, then, who will venture to assert, as mental philosophers often do assert, that the attributes which we ascribe to things are simply the phenomena or the sensations which they cause in us, must be prepared to deny all CHAP. i. THE PHYSICAL OBJECT OF SCIENCE 7 the imperceptible structures and motions which are recognised as attributes of things in natural philosophy. Natural philosophy does not stop at the reality and knowledge of imperceptible things and their imper ceptible attributes. It takes one step further : it regards the imperceptible as not only real but causal. In the first place, among imperceptible objects there are latent processes of cause and effect, no part of which can be represented by a sensible object. When, for example, the physicist declares that the medium called aether remains fixed in space, while each successive part of it undulates in consequence of the previous undulation of another part, in the same manner as water communi cates successive waves, he affirms that the whole of this propagation of undulations through aether is real, though the whole of it is imperceptible. Secondly, he affirms still more ; he affirms that the imperceptible undula tions not only cause one another, but finally cause our sensations of light. In this instance of light, as well as in the parallel case of heat, natural philosophy un hesitatingly accepts the conclusion that imperceptible motions of imperceptible things not only exist but cause our sensations. In other words, secondary qualities as existing in nature are insensible primary qualities which are causes of secondary qualities, as sensible in us. Natural philosophy is not a sham. One or other, or many, of its propositions, may be untrue. But its whole fabric of the physical, but insensible, world which causes the sensible image of it to arise in us, cannot be an invention. There is a thing beyond sense, a reality beyond phenomena, not only actual in nature, but known to science. There is a thing real and known which is not a sensible phenomenon, because such things as imperceptible particles are known really to PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. exist, though they are incapable of becoming sensible. There are attributes real and known which belong to this thing, but are not sensations or sensible phe nomena, because such attributes as the imperceptible motions of imperceptible particles are known really to take place, although they are not capable of becoming sensible. Finally, these real things by these real attributes are real and known causes of human sensa tions because the imperceptible motions of the imper ceptible are known really to cause sensations of light and other sensations in men, although the latent pro cess, by which an imperceptible motion such as the undulation of ether produces sensible light, is totally beyond the reach of sense, which perceives not the undulation but the sensible result. Thus real things and real attributes transcending yet really causing sensa tions are, in some way or other, known to the natural philosopher. The insensible, then, is not a simple reality, but contains three realities, all insensible : real substances, real attributes, real causes of sensations. There are things in themselves. A thing in itself might mean a thing out of all relations. In this sense nature contains no things in themselves ; it is a system of related things the universe of which is alone out of relation as the sum of all relations. But this is not what is meant by a thing in itself in philosophy : what is really meant is not a thing out of all relations, but a thing distinct from the phenomena it causes in us, a / thing in itself as opposed to its sensible appearance. In this meaning, nature contains infinitely more things in themselves than it contains phenomena ; and man, as a natural philosopher, knows things in themselves which are not phenomena, when he knows imperceptible particles ; knows not merely the phenomena which CHAP. I. THE PHYSICAL OBJECT OF SCIENCE (J they cause in us, but their real attributes, when he knows imperceptible motions, and knows that the thing in itself, not as an ' unknown cause,' but by its real attributes produces phenomena, when he knows that imperceptible things, by their imperceptible motions, cause human sensations. There are real things known, real attributes known, real causes known, beyond the phenomena of sense. All this knowledge does man as a natural philosopher possess of things in themselves. Two antitheses have been handed down to us from ancient philosophy, the natural and the supernatural, the visible and the invisible. These distinctions are often treated as convertible ; but they are not so. The natural and the visible are not identical ; and the super natural and the invisible are not identical : there is a natural yet invisible world. Between the extremes of visible nature and the invisible supernatural world there is an invisible nature, distinct from both ; a world which is neither in heaven nor in man, but in itself. If we combine both the antitheses, they cease to be double, and form this triple division :— 1. The natural and visible, e.g. sensible phenomena. 2. The natural and invisible, e.g. insensible bodies and imperceptible particles. 3. The supernatural and invisible, e.g. God. Natural philosophy is the science of nature visible and invisible. From the former it infers the latter. But it stops at nature. So far as it is the science of an invisible nature, it is a philosophy of the suprasensible, not a theology of the supernatural. It outruns sense, but walks with reason to knowledge, without flying to faith. That we know invisible nature beyond sense in natural philosophy is a simple fact, explicable by logical 10 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. reasoning from sense. Can we in theology further know the invisible beyond nature as well as beyond sense ? Can we know the supernatural world and God by reason ing from sense ? These are questions beyond natural philosophy. But the theologian may be sure that, on the one hand, unless we can vindicate our knowledge of insensible nature, we can hardly hope for a know ledge of an insensible world beyond nature ; and that, on the other hand, reasoning from sense to nature encourages reasoning from nature to God. Natural philosophy is the first step beyond sense into the unseen world, within which natural theology soars heaven wards to tell Of things invisible to mortal sight. I will conclude this chapter by quoting, from Sir John Herschel's ' Discourse on Natural Philosophy,' a passage which is sufficiently near to the existing state of science for our present purpose. Its value is that it groups together a number of scientific conclusions, which, as it seems to me, cannot be explained by any theory of reality except realism, or the theory that there is a real and known world beyond phenomena, or by any process of knowledge except syllogism, or deductive inference which carries reason beyond sense. ' What mere assertion will make any man believe, that in one second of time, in one beat of the pendulum of a clock, a ray of light travels over 192,000 miles, and would therefore perform the tour of the world in about the same time it requires to wink with our eve- lids, and in much less than a swift runner occupies" in taking a single stride ? What mortal can be made to believe, without demonstration, that the sun is almost a million times larger than the earth ; and that, although CHAP. i. THE PHYSICAL OBJECT OF SCIENCE 1 1 so remote from us that a cannon-ball shot directly towards it, and maintaining its full speed, would be twenty years in reaching it, it yet affects the earth by its attraction in an inappreciable instant of time ? a closeness of union of which we can form but a feeble and totally inadequate idea, by comparing it to any material connection ; since the communication of an impulse to such a distance, by any solid intermedium we are acquainted with, would require, not moments, but whole years. And when with pain and difficulty we have strained our imagination to conceive a distance so vast, a force so intense and penetrating, if we are told that the one dwindles to an insensible point, and the other is unfelt at the nearest of the fixed stars, from the mere effect of their remoteness, while among those very stars are some whose actual splendour exceeds by many hundred times that of the sun itself, although we may not deny the truth of the assertion, we cannot but feel the keenest curiosity to know how such things were made out. ' The foregoing are amongst those results of scientific research which, by their magnitude, seem to transcend oar power of conception. There are others again, which, from their minuteness, would elude the grasp of thought, much more of distinct and accurate measure ment. Who would not ask for demonstration, when told that a gnat's wing in its ordinary flight beats many hundred times in a second? or that there exist ani mated and regularly organised beings, many thousands of whose bodies laid close together would not extend an inch ? But what are these to the astonishing truths which optical inquiries have disclosed, which teach us that every point of a medium through which a ray of light passes is affected with a succession of periodical 1'2 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. movements, regularly recurring at equal intervals, no less than five hundred millions of millions of times in a single second ; that it is by such movements, communi cated to the nerves of our eyes, that we see — nay, more, that it is the difference in the frequency of the recur rence which affects us with the sense of the diversity of colour ; that, for instance, in acquiring the sensation of redness our eyes are affected four hundred and ei^htv- »/ o «/ two millions of millions of times ; of yellowness, five hundred and forty-two millions of millions of times ; and of violet, seven hundred and seven millions of millions of times ? Do not such things sound more like the ravings of madmen, than the sober conclusions of people in their waking senses ? ' They are, nevertheless, conclusions to which any one may most certainly arrive, who will only be at the trouble of examining the chain of reasoning by which they have been deduced ; but, in order to do this, something beyond the mere elements of abstract science is required. Waiving, however, such instances as these, which, after all, are rather calculated to surprise and astound, than for any other purpose, it must be ob served that it is not possible to satisfy ourselves com pletely that we have arrived at a true statement of any law of nature, until, setting out from such statement, and making it a foundation of reasoning, we can show, by strict argument, that the facts observed must follow from it as necessary logical consequences, and this not vaguely and generally, but with all possible precision in time, place, weight, and measure.' CHAT. IJ. CHAPTEE II. IDEALISM AND REALISM. THE problem of this essay is to use the insensible world of science as a fact from which to find the nature and origin of knowledge. Science is systematic know ledge. Yet the mental philosopher usually contents himself with endeavouring to explain ordinary know ledge. If he is a mental physiologist, it is true, he also uses natural science to proceed from the organs to the functions of sense. But there is another use of natural science to mental philosophy, which has been too much neglected : the objects of science are as important as the bodily organs to the explanation of knowledge. Natural science should be used to ascer tain what we know as well as how we know it. More over, the insensible physical world of the natural philosopher ought to prove to the mental philosopher that neither all knowable objects nor all sensible data are psychical, but some are physical. I purpose to show that physical objects of science, being objects of knowledge, require physical data of sense. Hence this essay is called Physical Eealism. We must confront natural with mental philosophy. The former has outstripped the latter. Natural philoso phers have long ago discovered to a great extent how physical nature is the causa essendi of sensible data ; but mental philosophers have failed altogether to show 14 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. how sensible data are the causa cognoscendi of physical nature. The reason is, the data are mainly unknown. The existing hypotheses of the origin of knowledge do not explain the facts of science, and too often end "by denying what they fail to explain. Especially to blame is the hypothesis that all the data of sense are psychical facts, such as sensations and ideas, from which there is no way to insensible but physical objects of scientific knowledge. This vicious hypothesis is psychological idealism. Hence this essay is designed to combat psychological idealism by means of physical realism, and to appeal from the hypothesis of psychical data to the physical objects of science. The physical world of science cannot be explained by the common hypothesis that all sensible data are psychical, nor without the more moderate hypothesis that some are physical. The motto of all idealism is ideate prius reale posterius. But it has many meanings. Anaxagoras founded philosophical idealism by the proposition that the Divine Intelligence is prior to the order of nature ; and in adding that soul is also prior to body Plato became its second founder. The Cartesian idealism means that knowledge begins with psychical ideas, and the Kantian idealism that it adds a priori mental ele ments. Of these idealisms two are of supereminent importance in the history of thought ; that which places God at the beginning of the world, and that which places psychical ideas at the beginning of knowledge. The former is the belief of the majority of mankind, the latter of most philosophers since Descartes. The former- is theological, the latter psychological idealism. Theological and psychological idealism are not necessarily connected. A philosopher may hold that God causes physical nature and man apprehends it. CHAP. Ti. IDEALISM AND REALISM 15 He may be theologically an idealist, psychologically a realist. On the other hand, he may suppose that all sensible data are psychical facts, and yet doubt the existence of God. He may be psychologically an idealist, theologically an atheist. The founders of natural theology had no thought of making psychical facts the beginnings of human knowledge. The followers of Hume hardly consider themselves supporters of the doctrine that God created the world. These distinctions are of importance, because there is a crude notion in our times that idealism in mental philosophy is necessary to theology. They are of special bearing on the scope of this essay, which is aimed, not at theo logical, but solely at psychological idealism. Psychological idealism began with the supposition of Descartes that all the immediate objects of knowledge are ideas. From Descartes it passed to Locke and Berkeley. But with Hume it changed its terms from ideas to impressions. Kant preferred phenomena, Mill sensations. The most usual terms of the present day are sensations, feelings, psychical phenomena, and states of consciousness. But the hypothesis has not changed its essence, though the idealists have changed their terms, — Verbum, non animum, mutant. They at least agree that all sensible data are psychical objects of some kind or other. The psychological idealists differ widely about the origin of knowledge from these psychical data. Some of them hold that there are a priori elements contributed by mind to the psychical data of sense, others that these supposed elements are a posteriori. But this difference about the origin does not prevent them from agreeing about the object of sense, which they alike hold to be some kind of psychical fact, whether idea, im- 16 PHYSICAL, REALISM PART i. pression, phenomenon, sensation, feeling or state of consciousness. There is a further difference among the idealists. Some of them, beginning with Descartes, believe that, though the immediate objects of sense are psychical, reality also includes physical facts. Others, beginning with Berkeley, reply that psychical data cannot yield physical objects, and therefore the psychical is all that is known to be real. The former divide reality into the psychical and the physical, the latter resolve it wholly into the psychical. The former have been called Cosmothetic Idealists, and the latter Absolute or Pure Idealists. But, while they differ only about the objects which can be mediately known, they still agree about the immediate data. Starting from the common hypo thesis that all sensible data are psychical, the cosmo- thetic idealist nevertheless believes in physical realities, but the absolute idealist denies or doubts them. Cosmothetic idealists further differ among themselves about the physical world. Descartes held that a physical world can be known through the medium of ideas ; Locke, in one of his many moods, that it is a cause of ideas, but unknown. This difference is important, because cosmothetic idealism is the usual view of men tal physiology in our own time, and it is held in both forms. Mental physiologists have unwarily received from psychologists the hypothesis of psychical data, which they usually call sensations, and have at the same time learnt from nature that the data of sense are effects of physical structures and motions beyond sense. Hence they are cosmothetic idealists. But according as they are rather physiologists or rather psychologists, they lean to Descartes or to Locke. The former hold that, starting from psychical sensations as CHAP. IT IDEALISM AND REALISM 17 data, by inference we know their physical causes ; the latter, that the psychical sensations are produced by the physical causes, which are nevertheless unknown and unknowable. Their differences, however, do not dis turb the consensus that the immediate objects of sense are not physical, but purely psychical. It may be thought that this consensus of idealism is a proof of truth. But agreement is one of the chief causes of human error, because it tempts men to dis pense with further consideration of the question. More over, we shall find that the inconsiderate assent to this common proposition is the very reason why opposite schools of idealists cannot conclusively answer one another. Lastly, there are two kinds of consensus : one, assent to a self-evident principle, such as 1-f 1 = 2 ; the other, agreement in a common hypothesis. Now the proposition that all sensible data are psychical phenomena is not a self-evident principle, but a de batable hypothesis. Eealism is the philosophy of a reality beyond psy chical facts. The earliest form in which it was a conscious doctrine was the belief in the reality of universals. Plato thought that there were universal forms existing in themselves, incorporeal and super natural archetypes, in accordance with which similar individuals are produced in nature. Aristotle agreed that there are real universal forms, and even that they are incorporeal substances. He contended, however, that they exist not in themselves but only^as belonging to individual substancesj_which are concretions of matter and form. TrT the Middle Ages the disciples of Plato and Aristotle were called Eeales, to distinguish them from the Nominales, who either contended that uni versals were merely general names, or else general c 18 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. conceptions. Those who adopted the latter view were afterwards called Conceptualists. It is not necessary to be either a Flatonist or an Aristotelian. There is a third realism of universals possible ; and that, too, without falling into nominalism or conceptualism. The theory of the reality of univer sals, though overlaid with many errors, contains two important truths. The first is, that science knows of classes which, have an indefinite number of similarities, such as triangles, colours, and living beings. The second is, that of these similarities some are fundamental, others derivative ; e.g. three-sided rectilineal figure is the foundation of innumerable other similarities of tri angle ; undulations of ether produce the facts of colour, metabolism is the basis of the facts of life. The first truth shows that a natural class, or real kind, is not a name, nor a notion, but a real sum of individuals form ing an indefinite number of similarities. The second truth shows that the distinction between essence and property is not a nominal difference depending on the meaning of a name, nor a notional difference depending on the analysis of a notion, but a real distinction depend ing on the fundamental character of the similarities, on which the rest depend. Without natural classes, whose similarities can be expressed in laws, there would be no science ; and without essences, or fundamental similarities of those natural classes on which other similarities depend, we could not have the mathematics of the triangle referring its propositions back to its being a three-sided figure, nor the physics of light? referring all the facts of colour back to the undulation of rcther. A natural class, then, is the sum of individuals possessing an indefinite number of similarities. A real CHAP. IT. IDEALISM AND REALISM 19 essence is the fundamental similarities of the individuals of a natural class. It is easy to make too much of it or too little. If we follow the nominalist, and make sethereal undulation the meaning of the name 'light,' or the conceptualist, and make it the analysis of the notion, we make too little of it, because the undulation of gether began before, goes on without, and will last after, our names and notions. If, on the other hand, we follow Aristotle, and make it an incorporeal sub stance coexisting with matter, we make too much of it, because it is only a motion of matter after all ; while, if we try to soar with Plato into the supernatural world and make it a heavenly archetype of earthly light, we fail to explain the facts and desert science for mysticism. The realism of universals, however, is not the business of this essay. There is another meaning of realism, which we may call the Eealism of Individuals. This is the theory that there is a physical world of individuals beyond psychical sensations and ideas. It may be held with any theory of universals ; the realist of individuals is not necessarily a realist of universals. It is also a later product. The realism of universals is rather a doctrine of ancient, the realism of individuals rather of modern, philosophers. Not that Aristotle rejected the distinct reality of physical individuals ; but it never occurred to him that it needed to be proved. There was, as Brandis remarked, an uncon scious realism in ancient philosophy. It seldom doubted a world beyond the psychical; the question was rather whether there were not three worlds; natural individuals, supernatural universals, and psychical in telligences. But in modern times the development of psychological idealism has brought even the physical c 2 20 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. world of individuals into question. In opposition to this psychological idealism a conscious realism has arisen, the object of which is to show that there are physical things beyond psychical facts. This realism of physical individuals is part of the business of this essay, and for shortness will in the sequel be called simply Realism. Realism is constantly misunderstood. It is some times supposed to be a synonym for mere Sensualism, or the belief that physical things are as they appear to our senses. But sensualism is only a crude form of realism. There is a realism which goes beyond sense to science, and holds that things are not as they imme diately appear to sense, but rather as they are mediately inferred by science. A more serious misunderstanding is the confusion of realism with Materialism. Material ism is a kind of realism ; it is also more. It is a double hypothesis : first, that there are physical things ; secondly, that they are either the only realities, or at least are prior to psychical realities, whether in nature or in man. Only the first part of this hypothesis is essential to realism ; the second part, which contains, too, the real sting of the materialist, is unnecessary to the realist. A man ceases to be a materialist, but he remains a realist, if he holds that God is the Creator and Governor of the world, while the world is not a psychical fact of God's Intelligence but a physical effort of His Intelligent Will ; and that nature is posterior to God though prior to man. The motto of materialism is, reale prius ideale posterius : the motto of realism is reale non est ideale. In short, it is one thing to affirm a natural world of individual objects beyond sense, another thing to deny a supernatural world beyond nature. CHAP. II. IDEALISM AND REALISM 21 Hence realism is not the exact contrary of all idealism. It is not opposed at all to the idealism of natural theology. It is not even the direct contrary to all psychological idealism. Idealism centres itself on the data, realism on the objects of knowledge. The former says that all sensible data are psychical, the latter that some objects are physical. Hence a difficulty in contrasting them, and even in keeping them distinct. Some idealists, as we have seen, though they regard all data as psychical, admit the independent reality of physical objects. As Hamilton has pointed out, the cosmothetic idealists are also hypothetical, or, as some would say, transfigured realists. The exact contrary of realism is not all idealism but pure or absolute idealism. The pure or absolute idealist denies the reality of aught beyond the psychical world, the realist affirms the reality of the physical. At the same time realism is not a single body of doctrines. Eealists agree only in one position — the reality of physical things. In the foundations of that position, in the sensible data of knowledge, they differ toto ccelo. It is, therefore, necessary to classify them to prevent confusion, and that sort ofignoratio elenchi,wbich idealism and realism alike have to suffer from their opponents when they are not properly defined. Of the realism of individuals there are two species recognised among modern philosophers — the Hypo thetical Eealism of the cosmothetic idealists, and the Intuitive or Natural Eealism of the Scotch philosophers, Eeid, Stewart, and Hamilton. Agreeing about know- able objects, hypothetical and intuitional realists differ about the data of sense. According to the former, the data are psychical ideas or sensations of the ego ; ac cording to the latter, they include the primary qualities PHYSICAL HEALISM TAUT I. of the physical non-ego. Agreeing in a physical world, they differ about the way in which it is to be reached, the former holding that it is inferred from psychical data, the latter, that it is immediately perceived. Hypo thetical or transfigured realism is the hypothesis that our senses present psychical ideas or sensations repre senting external physical objects ; intuitive or natural realism, the hypothesis that the senses present the pri mary qualities of external physical objects themselves. Modern philosophy exhibits a constant oscillation between the opposite poles of the ego and the non-ego ; and the two received kinds of realism are opposite cur rents in this oscillation. The cosmothetic idealist or hypothetical realist, learning from natural philosophy that his senses do not directly perceive external things, takes refuge in the psychical world of his own soul. Dissatisfied with this alternative, and conscious that he somehow apprehends something physical, the in tuitional realist flies forward to the direct perception of an external world. Extreme views are usually as untrue as extreme measures are dangerous. Is there a via media ? I venture to propose a new Eealism. When I consider the objects of science, I am struck by the enormous number of things and attributes entirely beyond the reach of sense and not even corresponding to any sensible object, I refer, espe cially, to corpuscles, their structures and motions. Secondly, on going further, I find that the whole ex ternal world has been discovered by sciences, such as optics, acoustics, and biology, to be insensible, and that nothing is sensible except what has been impressed on the body, and in the body on the nervous system, of a sentient being. Thirdly, I notice that a connection has been scientifically established between external in- CHAP. II. IDEALISM AND REALISM 23 sensible objects and the objects of which I am sensible. The former are causes of the latter. They are also found to resemble one another in primary qualities, such as duration, extension, motion, but not in secondary qualities, such as light, heat, and -sound; for the se condary qualities, as they are in external nature, are found by corpuscular science to be insensible modes of primary qualities ; light, heat, and sound being all insensible modes of motion producing a heterogeneous effect on the senses. I cannot believe that this whole fabric of insensible objects can be scientific, yet unknown. But it must be either physical or psychical. If the objects are psy chical, they are either sensations or ideas. But they are insensible and often inconceivable. Now what is insensible cannot be a sensation, and what is incon ceivable cannot be an idea. Not all objects of science, then, are either sensations or ideas ; therefore they are not psychical objects at all. It remains that they are physical objects. Again, I cannot believe that this whole fabric of physical objects of science can have been inferred without sufficient data of sense. I therefore proceed to inquire what data of sense are required to infer a physical object of science. This is a question of logic. Now the rules of logic teach me that whatever is inferred is inferred from similar data. If I infer that all men will die, it is because similar men have died. Now, as we have seen, physical objects are scientifically inferred from sensible data. It follows that the sensible objects, which are these data, must also be physical. The similar can be inferred only from the similar, therefore the physical can be inferred only from the physical. This conclusion, however, places me in a dilemma. 24 PHYSICAL REALISM PART Science shows me that the object of sense is internal, logic that it is physical. The former evidence might incline me to cosmothetic idealism, the latter to intui tive realism. Which shall I prefer ? Am I to say that the sensible data are psychical objects within me ? No, because I require physical data of sense to infer physical objects of science. Am I to say that the sensible data are physical objects without me? No, because no external object is sensible. I can be neither a cosmothetic idealist, because of logic, nor an intuitive realist, because of natural science. If, then, natural science requires that the object of sense must be within my nervous system in order to be sensible, and logic that it must be physical in order to infer physical objects of science in the external world, how can the sensible object be at once physical and internal ? I answer, it is the nervous system itself sensibly affected. The hot felt is the tactile nerves heated, the white seen is the optic nerves so coloured. The sensible object must be distinguished from its external cause on the one hand, and on the other hand from the internal operation of apprehending it : it is the intermediate effect in the nerves produced by the external cause, and apprehended by the operation of sensation. In particular, the operation and the object of sensation must not be confused, because the former may be psychical, the latter is physical. There is some plausibility in saying that the act of consciously touch ing is psychical, there is none at all in saying that the hot felt is psychical. Non sequitur. Vision may be a psychical sensation, but the white seen is a physical object. Nor is there any reason why a psychical opera tion should not apprehend a physical object. The sen sible object then is identical neither with the external CHAP. ii. IDEALISM AND REALISM 25 cause nor with the internal operation of sensation. It is the effect in the nervous system produced by the one and apprehended by the other. For example, the hot felt and the white seen are produced by external objects and are apprehended by internal sensations of touch and vision, but are themselves respectively the tactile and the optic nerves sensibly affected in the manner apprehended as hot and white. From such sensible data, internal, as science re quires, and physical, as logic requires, man infers physical objects in the external world by parity of reasoning. Men in general begin by inferring that physical objects of sense are produced by physical causes exactly similar. Thus from the hot within we infer a fire without. Such objects, directly inferred to correspond with sensible data, may be called the originals represented by them. They are inferred, but are generally said to be perceived ; thus we speak of perceiving the fire though we only infer it. We may, perhaps, say then that the originals of the sensible are insensible objects inferentially perceptible. Afterwards, scientific men carry on this parity of reasoning, and infer that these originals beyond sense consist of further insensible particles similar to the originals, but not at all represented by sensible data ; and that many other objects, such, for example, as the side of the moon always turned from the earth, are incapable of producing sensible objects in us. These unrepresented objects may be said to be not only in sensible but imperceptible, and are objects of an infer ence which may be called transcendental, in the sense of transcending both sensitive and inferential perception. Lastly, science also finds that in another direction the ordinary man has carried his inferences from 20 PHYSICAL REALISM PA.RT I. similar data to similar objects too fur. Physical objects are found to be like sensible in their primary, not in their secondary qualities ; for instance, external motion is like sensible motion, but external heat is an imper ceptible mode of motion while sensible heat is not sensibly a motion at all. How is -this inferred? Because, though at first sight sensible heat would demand a similar external object, when all the facts of sensible heat are accumulated they are found to be the kind of facts that are only produced by motion. Hence from sensible physical data we scientifically infer insensible physical objects, like sensible objects in primary but unlike in secondary qualities. Such is the realism proposed in this essay. It may be expressed in two propositions : there are physical objects of science in the external world ; therefore there are, as data to infer them, physical objects of sense in the internal nervous system. It is a via media between intuitive realism and the hypothetical realism of the cosmothetic idealist. As it recognises physical realities, it is realism. As the objects, which it sup poses to be sensible, are not external but internal, it is not intuitive realism. As the objects of sense, which it supposes to be the data of inferring an external physical world, are not psychical but physical, it is not hypothetical realism. As they are physical data within, to infer physical objects without, the realism which I advocate may be called Physical Eealism. There are three realistic ways of explaining our knowledge of an external physical world. The first is cosmothetic idealism, which supposes that we are sen sible of a psychical, but infer a physical world. This is against logic, which shows that all inference is by similarity. The second is intuitive realism, which CIIAr. IT. IDEALISM AND REALISM 27 supposes that we directly perceive an external physical world. This is against natural philosophy, which shows that we perceive nothing directly but what is propagated into our nervous system. The third is physical realism, which supposes that we sensibly perceive an internal but physical world, from which we infer an external and physical world. This agrees with both natural philosophy and logic. Physical Eealism must be especially distinguished from intuitive, or, as it is also called, natural realism. It is true that the theories have some common points. This essay owes to Eeid the instructive remark on the ' Sentiments of Bishop Berkeley,' that there is no evi dence for the doctrine ' that all the objects of knowledge are ideas in my own mind.'1 The rejection of idealism, the reality of the physical world, the belief in a phy sical object of sense, and the possibility that a psychical subject may apprehend a physical object, are all points in intuitive realism which find a place in physical realism. But here the agreement ends. The intuitive realist holds an immediate perception of a physical world outside. I distinguish the immediate perception of the physical world within, and the inferential per ception of the physical world beyond myself. The intuitive realist follows the idealist in thinking too much of the sensible data, and too little of the insensible objects of science. He gives too much weight to consciousness, and too little to science, or rather too much to the ordinary and too little to the scientific consciousness. He appeals to common sense, which is the problem rather than the solution of philo sophy. He elevates the dicta of consciousness and 1 Eeid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers. Essay II., chap. x. p. 283 (ed. Hamilton). 28 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. common sense from unanalysed facts into self-evident principles. Hence, in asserting an immediate know ledge of external nature lie contradicts science. But we must appeal from common sense to universal science, and from ordinary to scientific realism. The idealist can never be answered by asserting the reality of the sensible world, which he admits, and, if it stood alone, could explain. He must be confronted with the in sensible world of science. The intuitive realists have an impossible theory of the data of sense, comprised of two incompatible ex tremes. On the one hand, they admit the idealistic position that secondary qualities, as sensible, are psy chical sensations ; on the other hand, they assert that external primary qualities of the non-ego are imme diately perceived. The admission is fatal, because the Berkeleian at once points out that primary qualities are apprehended in the same way as secondary, and there fore if one set, as sensible, are psychical sensations, why not the other ? The assertion is equally fatal, because scientific analysis shows that nothing external is imme diately perceived. Hence I retract the admission and reject the assertion. Whether directed to primary or to secondary qualities, sense apprehends neither a sen sation nor an external object, but an internal object in the nervous system. Everything external is inferred. Perhaps the chief reason of the defect in intuitive realism is the confusion of object and non-ego. Object is the res considerata apprehended either by sense or by reason. It is not always an external object. In sense, it is always internal, whether it be the hot or the moving, the white or the extended, secondary or primary. In reasoning, it is external, whenever we infer something beyond the sensible object within us. But the intuitive CHAP. ii. IDEALISM AND REALISM 29 realists, having confused object and non-ego , supposed that whenever sense has an object it presents the non-ego. Keally, sense always apprehends an object distinct from the operation, but never a non-ego distinct from the ego, that is, the man himself. Hence, also, their erroneous belief that in apprehending a primary quality, as an object, sense presents a quality of the non-ego, and in not apprehending a secondary quality as it is in the non-ego, it presents no object. Eeally, as sensible, both primary and secondary qualities are apprehended as objects, but not as external. For example, the sensibly hot and moving are both apprehended as objects by sense, but entirely within the sentient being. The subordination of secondary to primary quali ties is not at all in the sensible effects, but in the external causes. In the external world, secondary qualities are found by science to be only specific varieties of primary qualities. In the internal world, all qualities appear to sense to be equally elementary. As sensible, a primary quality, such as motion, is not in the non-ego, and a secondary quality, such as heat, is not a mere sensation ; nor are they both sensations ; but they are both sensible objects, both internal to the sentient being, both physical, both parts of the nervous substance sensibly affected, both apprehended in the same way as objects by the operation called ' sensation.' From these qualities, all apprehended in exactly the same way as sensible objects in our nervous system, the ordinary man infers a complete correspondence of qualities out side, the scientific man partly corrects him by reducing secondary qualities to primary qualities in the external world. The relativity of knowledge has become a common place. Is it a fact ? A sensible effect is the result of 30 PHYSICAL REALISM PART T. the combination of two causes. As active or efficient cause, the external world produces the sensible effect in the nervous system ; as passive or material cause, the nervous system receives this effect according to its susceptibility. Hence the effect is like or unlike to the efficient causes, according to the varying susceptibility of the nervous system. There is a variation in different animals and in different men, and even in the same man at different times. But in all men there is one differ ence of main importance. The nervous system is far more susceptible of similar effects from primary than from secondary qualities. It is more capable of re flecting the waves of the sea than the undulations of gether. Not that the effect is wholly alike in primary or wholly unlike in secondary qualities. The primary quality of distance is imperfectly reproduced in sense, the secondary quality of aerial vibration is to some small extent represented in the sense of hearing. But, on the whole, there is a general similarity of the sensible to the external in primary, and a general dissimilarity in secondary qualities, because of the inferior susceptibility of the nervous system to receive like effects from the latter qualities in external objects. In the sense, then, that the sensible effect only partly depends on the external efficient cause, and partly also on the matter of the nervous system, there is a rela tivity of knowledge to the structure of the nerves. There is also an evolution, which consists in the in creasing adaptation of the nerves to sustain the effect under the action of the external object. On the other hand, by the relativity of knowledge it is generally meant that the sensible effect produced is a psychical fact, not partly but wholly heterogeneous to the physical object, if there be one. In this sense CHAP. ir. IDEALISM AND REALISM 31 physical realism is opposed to the relativity of know ledge. It is true that red refuses to appear to our senses as a motion representing the external motion which produces it. But the cause of this fact is to IK; found in the construction of the optic nerve, which, when acted on by a certain imperceptible motion of aether, receives a sensible colour apparently unlike motion, just as oxygen and hydrogen in certain pro portions, when acted on by electricity, become water. In the same way, when a wheel rotates too quickly, the sensible effect ceases to be a motion, because the nerves are insusceptible of taking on so rapid a motion in sense. The sensible effect is similar or dissimilar to the external object, so far as the nervous system is capable or incapable of being affected similarly to the external object. There is no occasion then to resort to the hypothesis of a psychical relativity : the nervous element is sufficient. Moreover, if there were a psychical relativity, it would be ineradicable, because the sensible effect would then be completely heterogeneous, and would there fore supply no data of inference to an external physical cause. Eeally, sensible effects are partly like and partly unlike the external causes, because the nerves are partly fitted and partly unfitted to represent them. Being partly like, the nervous unfitness to re present secondary qualities as they are in nature is being constantly eliminated by scientific reasoning. Thus, sense sometimes presents motion as motion, but cannot help presenting the hot, the red, &c., as heterogeneous to motion, because of the structure of the sensory nerves ; science, by comparing sensible motion with the sensible facts of the hot, the red, &c., infers that the external cause of the latter is really a 32 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. mode of motion. In secondary qualities the sensible effect is heterogeneous, but the cause inferred by science is identical with the external object. Not that scien tific elimination of the defects of sense ever becomes so complete as to end in absoluteness of knowledge. But there is a constant progress towards making science the mirror of being. Sense starts with physical data partly like and partly unlike external nature ; science, by progressive inferences, tends more and more to dis cover the external qualities which cause not only the like but the unlike data in the nervous system. The sensible, therefore, is not a psychical effect completely heterogeneous to the external physical cause, but a physical effect partly relative to the nervous system ; and science is perpetually correcting this partial re lativity. It is usual to divide theories of sensation and per ception into presentative and representative. There are two presentative theories, respectively characterising the pure idealist and the intuitive realist. The former holds that there is no distinction between sensation and perception : sense, according to him, immediately per ceives psychical facts, which are the sum of known existing objects. The latter distinguishes sensation and perception, because he distinguishes the psychical and the physical : sensation, in his view, is limited to psychical sensations, perception immediately apprehends the pri mary qualities of an external physical world. The pure idealist says, ' What I see is what exists ; ' the intui tive realist, ' What exists I see : ' the former reduces nature to perception, the latter brings perception to nature ; one holds esse is percipi, the other esse per- cipitur. But the point is that, according to both, the real is the sensible world, which is directly presented, CHAP. II. IDEALISM AND REALISM 33 not represented, in perception, without an inference to an external original. The representative theory, on the other hand, distinguishes the data of sense, as pre sented, from the external world, as represented, in perception. It exists in many forms, according to various theories of the data of sense. But the current form is that of cosmothetic idealism, which holds that sense presents psychical data of some kind, representing physical objects in the external world. Physical realism must accept the representative theory, but not in its idealistic form. The data pre sented to sense are internal, yet not psychical. They are physical parts of the nervous system, tactile, optic, auditory, &c., sensibly affected in various manners, repre senting, but only partly resembling, the external world. Further, in sense, the object is not the operation, the hot is not touch, the white is not vision, the loud is not hearing. From these points I form the following theory of sensation. In that the sensible object is internal, sen sation is not the immediate apprehension of an external object. In that the sensible object is physical, sensation is not the immediate apprehension of a psychical fact. In that it is the immediate apprehension of an object, though internal, it is a kind of perception. I should define sensation, or sensitive perception, as the im mediate apprehension of an internal physical object within the nervous system of a sentient being. But perception cannot be confined to sensation. Although it is true that sense feels the hot, and reason infers the fire, everybody talks of perceiving the fire. The philosopher will find it vain to fly in the face of the universal language not only of ordinary life but even of science. He must recognise this perception and analyse it. There is, then, besides sensitive or L> 34 PHYSICAL REALISM PART I. immediate perception, inferential or mediate perception. The former is limited to the internal object of sense, the latter extends to the external original. Moreover, so long as we remember that there is an inference in this latter operation, the term ' perception ' not only does no harm but serves to mark a most important distinction. We first infer external originals of sensible objects, e.g. the fire, the sea, &c. ; we cannot be said to see, but we may be said to perceive, these external objects, and also to observe and experience them, though indirectly. Afterwards, we go on to infer other external objects not represented by any sensible object, e.g. a corpuscle, aether : these we cannot be said either to see or per ceive ; they are not only insensible but imperceptible, and we infer them by reasoning which transcends per ception. In short, we must distinguish sensitive perception, inferential perception, and transcendental inference. Hence the following classification of physical objects knowable, and of the operations concerned with them : — 1. Internal parts of the nervous system sensibly affected: sensible data : immediately perceptible, objects of sense, or of sensitive perception, observation, ex perience. E.g. the sensibly moving, the sensibly hot. External parts of the universe: insensible objects : objects of inference. (1) Originals represented by sensible objects, and resembling them in primary not in secondary qualities: insensible but mediately perceptible objects of inferential perception, observation, experience. E.g. the fire, the waves of the sea. CHAP. ii. IDEALISM AND REALISM 35 (2) Objects unrepresented, though causing some sensible objects by imperceptible secondary qualities : the imperceptible : objects of trans cendental inference. E.g. corpuscles, the undulations of aether. This essay contemplates not only a new realistic hypo thesis, but a different method from that usually used in mental philosophy. Every philosophy must have a beginning. But the beginning must be what is best known ; and in mental philosophy the present objects of science are better known than the original data of sense. The method in use takes too direct a way of getting at the original data. It is true that the beginnings of human knowledge are sensible data. But the philosopher does not stand at the beginning of human knowledge. Philosophy did not begin with the infancy of the human race. The philosopher cannot observe his own infancy. The sensible data have long since been overlaid with an immense mass of inferences. Hence, though man may have begun once, it is impos sible for the philosopher to begin now, with the data. Yet most books on knowledge begin with the dogmatic assertion that the immediate objects of the senses are psychical sensations, from which they proceed to allow man as much knowledge of nature as can be squeezed out of the original hypothesis. But the assertion itself must be proved. Besides the induction of causation, we may either reason synthetically from cause to effect, or analytically from effect to cause. But the latter is the more usual method, because man knows so much more about facts than about their causes. Hence the order of science is usually the reverse of the order of nature. D 2 36 PHYSICAL REALISM TART I. Nature always proceeds from cause to effect, science usually from effect to cause ; so that science becomes an analysis of the synthesis of nature. Similarly, the order of mental philosophy is the reverse of the order of human knowledge. It is true that the order of human knowledge is from cause to effect in the sense that sensible data are the causes cog- noscendi of physical knowledge. We begin with them as children ; hence also we are tempted to begin with them again as psychologists. But the procedure is fallacious ; we must begin with the more knowable. Now every mental philosopher is an adult man, and every adult man is more certain what he now knows, than how he originally came to know it, of the dis coveries of science than of ' the secret springs and principles by which the human mind is actuated in its operation,' of the known objects than of the sensible data. Accordingly, as, in the science of nature, we must generally begin with present facts and go back wards to the causes essendi, so, in the science of know ledge, we must generally begin with the facts of scientific knowledge and go backwards to the causa? cognoscendi. Modern philosophers have made the mis take of attempting to repeat the synthesis of know ledge from the original data of the child and the race. But we must rather retrace our steps from the present to the past; instead of trying to follow the synthesis of knowledge from an unknown beginning, we must make an analysis from the present objects of scientific knowledge to the original data of sense. In a word, our method must be an analysis from science to sense. Hence, I began with attempting to give an outline of the kind of objects recognised in science. This CHAP. ii. IDEALISM AND REALISM 37 beginning lias several advantages. First, science is knowledge ; hence to begin with its objects is an appeal not from knowledge to reality, but from the data to the objects of knowledge. It is not a dogmatic assertion of what is, but an historical description of what is known. Secondly, science is knowledge at its widest extent, knowledge proceeding from the sensible through the insensible, but perceptible, to the imperceptible world. Hence we get a more extended view of know- able objects than that usually attained by mental philosophers, who tend to concentrate themselves on the world of sense and perception. Thirdly, science is knowledge at its best, whereas the hypotheses of mental philosophers about sensible data can hardly be called knowledge at all. In appealing from the hypothetical origin of knowledge to what is actually known in science, we are appealing from the less known to the more known. In short, we are getting the facts of knowledge, wherewith to test our hypothesis of its causes. The next step is analytically to find the sensible data required to cause the knowledge of the objects of science as facts. All theories of the sensible data and of the origin of knowledge, idealistic and realistic, must be treated and compared as hypotheses. We must ask, indeed, what is their direct evidence, but also and mainly whether they account for the knowledge of the objects of science. The general examination of these hypotheses will follow in the next chapter. Afterwards, the various hypotheses of Psychological Idealism will be taken in detail. The elimination of these hypotheses will finally bring us to Physical Eealism. Philosophy began with the external object, which was first of all treated as a pure reality by the Pre-So- cratic philosophers. Gradually it came to be regarded 38 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. as also an object of knowledge, a view which culminated with Aristotle. Aristotle's method was essentially to be gin with being as being, then to consider it secondarily as a knowable object, and thus to proceed from the known object to the knowing subject. Objective are generally the foundation of subjective distinctions in his writings. Descartes revolutionised philosophy by beginning with the conscious subject and passing through its conscious operations to the object apprehended. From his time the general order of mental philosophy has been syn thetic, from the subjective operations to the objective world. I propose to revert to the old order, and pro ceed analytically from object to subject, but in a new ^ spirit. Ancient philosophy rightly began with the object, but considered it too much as being, and too little as known. Consequently, it had a tendency to multiply entities without considering whether they are knowable. Hence the Cartesian revolution and the synthetic method from subject to object. But after the first consciousness, I think, the object is on the whole better known than the subject ; else natural philosophy would not be more advanced than mental philosophy. In order to avoid at once the dogmatism of ancient, and the doubtfulness of modern, philosophy, I propose to begin with the object, not as being, but as known in science, the most perfect form of knowledge. I proceed to ask what sensible objects are required as data for science to X know these objects. Of the knoAving subject I treat only so far as it bears on the objects known by sense and reason, because, though I know well that I am, I know less what I am than what I know. The ancient method from being to knowing was the right order, though too dogmatic in application. The modern CHAP. IT. IDEALISM AND REALISM 3D method inaugurated by Descartes, from the subject through the data of sense to the objects of science, was, after its first step, fallacious, because it then proceeded synthetically from the less to the more knowable. The analytic method of physical realism, without neglecting direct evidences of the data, proceeds, on the whole, from the more knowable objects of science to the less knowable data of sense. TABLE OF IDEALISM AND REALISM. IDEALISM. KEALISM. (1)A11 sensible (1) All sensible (1) All sensible (1) Some sensible data are psy- data are psy- data are inter- data are exter- chical. chical. nal but some nal and physi- are physical. cal. (2) All objects ( 2) Some objects (2) Some objects (2) Some objects knowable' are are physical. of science are are physical. psychical. physical. 40 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. CHAPTEE III. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE. Nihil est in intellectu, quod non prius in sensu. How far is this time-honoured' proposition true? As we have seen, it is not true of the objects of science. The whole physical world is beyond the reach of sense, insensible ; the corpuscles, of which it consists, are beyond the reach of inferential perception, imperceptible. It is true that objects of science are similar to sensible objects, but they are not the same. They are objects of intellect which are inferred from sensible objects but have never been in sense. But even this more modest statement must be qualified. In the first place, it requires Locke's correction that knowledge has two sources — sensation and reflection, outer and inner sense, or sense and consciousness. We immediately apprehend not only the objects of, or rather in, our senses, but also ourselves apprehending those objects, and performing many other conscious operations. Secondly, there is also a simpler source than sensation — the feelings. We immediately feel pleased and pained, and that too without apprehending any object ; as in the pain of hunger, the pleasure of nutrition. Sensation is more complex than feeling, be cause it is the apprehension of an object ; touch the apprehension of the hot, vision of the coloured, hearing of the sounding, &c. Frequently we have a feeling and CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 41 a sensation together ; for example, when we feel pleased or pained at the same time as we taste sweet or bitter. But it is of the greatest importance to distinguish feeling as a source of knowledge, especially as it is not at all improbable that it was the original source even of sensa tion. Even now that feeling and sensation are distinct, feelings are still the raw experiences of volitions, passions the beginnings of actions. We feel pleasure and pain before we will to pursue the one and avoid the other. All knowledge, then, does not begin with sensation, but with feeling, sensation, reflection. It is true, however, that all knowledge of nature begins with sensation. Yet even this modified proposition must be carefully guarded. In the first place, though phy sical knowledge begins with the operation of sensation, it does not follow that the object, in apprehending which the operation of sensation consists, is also a sensation. Yet this non-sequitur appears in the first few pages of most books of modern philosophy. The causes of the confusion of sensation with its object are to be found partly in the structure of modern languages, which, being far richer in abstract than in concrete terms, tempt philosophers to fall into a loose way of speaking of perceiving a sensation instead of perceiving a sensible object ; but mainly in another confusion, that of object and non-ego, which makes philosophers shrink from speaking of perceiving a sensible object, lest they should seem to assert an intuition of the external world. But an object (TO avTLKeiptvov) is merely that which is apprehended as opposed to the operation of apprehend ing it, and is not necessarily external to the apprehend ing subject. In sense, without being external, the object is still distinguishable from the operation ; the hot from touch, the sweet from taste, the coloured from 42 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. vision, the loud from hearing, the scented from smelling. Although, therefore, physical knowledge begins with sensation as an operation, it does not begin with sensa tion as a sensible object. Given, then, that physical knowledge begins with sense, we still have to ask, what is the object apprehended immediately by sensation ; what is the sensibly hot, sweet, coloured, loud, scented ? This is the question of the present chapter. There are two main evidences of hypothesis — the direct and the indirect. Direct evidence is the best, if possible, but it is seldom attainable ; for example, there is no direct evidence for the hypothesis of gether. But where direct proof fails, indirect should be all the stronger in compensation. It consists in using the facts to test the hypothesis, and that in two ways. First, the facts must be explained by the hypothesis ; secondly, they must eliminate other explanations. Thus the hypothesis of an undulating aether, as the vehicle of light, though wanting in direct evidence, is proved by its power of explaining all the facts of light, and by the elimination of the hypothesis of emission, which explains some, but not all the facts. I propose to apply these rules to the various hypotheses of sensible data, stated in the last chap ter. Are the objects of sense, which form the data of science, psychical or physical ; and, if physical, ex ternal or internal ? On the one hand, how far is there direct evidence for any of these hypotheses ? On the other hand, how do they stand the indirect test of the facts of science ? That is, can the objects of science as facts of knowledge be explained by any hypothesis of the data of sense ; and can the other hypotheses be eliminated ? Being hypotheses, idealism and realism alike must be treated by the logical rules CHAT. III. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 43 of hypothesis. Sensible data must be made to explain the scientific facts, as aethereal undulations have been made to explain luminous facts. We must be on our guard against synthetic hypothesis. What would be thought of a natural philosopher, who dared to start with the hypothesis of emission and denied all the facts of light, which cannot be deduced from the emission of corpuscles by a luminous body ? What, then, shall we think of mental philosophers, who start with the hypothesis of sensations and deny all the insensible world which cannot be deduced from the contempla tion of sensations by sensation? I admit that there may be direct evidence of an hypothesis. But even so, unless that evidence be mathematical certainty, the hypothesis must also be submitted to the indirect or analytical evidence of explaining the facts. Now it cannot be pretended that the direct evidence of the hypothesis of perceiving sensations or any other hypo thesis of sensible data is mathematically certain. There fore all the hypotheses of idealism and realism must pass through the alembic of analysis. The first direct evidence is that of consciousness. Consciousness is the immediate apprehension of oneself performing some operation. Thus I am conscious that I feel, that I perceive through my senses, that I imagine, remember, reason, desire, will, act. Unfor tunately, however, this operation of apprehending other operations has come to be confused in psychology with the operations themselves. Hamilton, seeing that perception requires an object, and consciousness of perception requires perception, falsely concluded that the consciousness includes the perception of the object, whereas it only requires it as a condition. He com mitted the common fallacy of confusing a thing with 44 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. its condition. Eeally, perception is the apprehension of the object, consciousness of perception the apprehen sion that I am apprehending the object. Mill, again, seeing that feeling pleasure and pain are the same as being conscious of feeling them, falsely concluded that every operation is the same as its consciousness. He committed the fallacy of over-generalisation. In feeling pleasure and pain there is no distinction between opera tion and object, and hence none between feeling and consciousness. But whenever there is a distinction between operation and object, the operation is concerned with the object and the consciousness with the operation. Hence to see white is different from being conscious of seeing white. So with other operations. Reasoning is a mediate operation from premises to conclusion. The consciousness of reasoning is an immediate apprehension that I am performing that mediate operation. Will is an active operation, the determination to act ; its consciousness an intellectual operation, apprehending that I determine to act. To reason and to will, then, are not the same as being conscious that I reason and will. It is not improbable that the lowest potency of sensi tive life may have been mere feeling, and the beginning of consciousness mere conscious feeling ; and that as, in the growth of the senses, the operation and the object became distinguished, consciousness became distinct from the operation, the operation being concerned with the object, and the consciousness with that relation of oneself to the object, in which an operation about an object consists. But whatever may have been the genesis of consciousness, its nature consists not in being the sense of objects but the sense of operations. When, as in feeling, there is no distinction between operation CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 45 and object, there is none between consciousness and operation. When, as in sensation, there is a distinction between operation and object, the operation is con cerned with the object, the consciousness with the opera tion. Not that consciousness has no reference to the object, but only that it is not the apprehension of it. The operation, which is the apprehension of the object, is a certain relation of subject to object : the conscious ness, which apprehends the operation, is an apprehension not of the object, but of the relation of the subject to the object. For example, I see white, I am conscious that I am seeing white. It was necessary to have thus defined consciousness on account of the mass of confusion and inconsequence imported into psychology by regarding consciousness as identical with all the conscious operations. Hamilton, seeing that consciousness is intuitive, but falsely identi fying it with the perception of an external world, falsely concludes that perception of an external world is also intuitive. He ought by the same argument to have made reasoning immediate, or else consciousness mediate, either of which alternatives is absurd. Mill, seeing that consciousness is limited to the apprehension of mental operations, and falsely identifying it with the mental operations, falsely concludes that the mental operation of sensation is also limited to the apprehension of mental operations. He might as well have said that will, being identical with its consciousness, is an intel lectual apprehension of a mental operation. But as will is an active determination to do something, while its consciousness is an intellectual apprehension that one has that active determination, so sensation is an appre hension of an object, while its consciousness is an apprehension that one is performing that operation. 46 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. Sensation says, ' This is white or sweet ' ; consciousness says, ' I am seeing something white or tasting something sweet.' This being consciousness, one operation of which I am conscious is that I know objects. What knowledge of objects am I conscious of possessing ? In answering this question, it must be remembered that science is a kind of knowledge of which we are conscious. There is an ordinary consciousness and a scientific consciousness. The ordinary man thinks little or nothing about it, but the man of science is conscious that science passes beyond sense into the insensible, and beyond the objects represented by sense into what I have called the im perceptible world. We are conscious of knowing a sensible, an insensible, and an imperceptible world by natural philosophy. Now, this knowledge does not appear to conscious ness to apprehend a psychical object. When I reflect on my inferential knowledge of the number of corpuscles in a drop of water, or of the distance of the sun from the earth, or of the size of the earth ; when, again, I reflect on my indirect perception of a fire, or the waves of the sea ; when, finally, I reflect on my sensation of the white object I see or the hot object I feel ; in all three instances, I appear to my consciousness to be apprehending not psychical, but physical facts. The conscious subject maybe psychical, the conscious opera tions may be psychical ; but I am not conscious that the vision of white, or the perception of a fire, or the inference of a corpuscle, apprehends a psychical object. So far as I am conscious of the sensations of my five senses, a white object in vision, a hot object in touch, a scent in my nostrils, a sound in my ears, a flavour in 'my mouth, cannot but seem to be apprehended as CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 47 physical objects. Consciousness of the apprehension of objects is in favour of realism. But when I apprehend the white, the hot, a scent, a sound, even a flavour, I further appear to be appre hending an object not only physical, but also external to myself. This seemingly conscious appearance is the strong point of intuitive realism, which depends on it to claim an intuition of an external world. Nevertheless, the appearance is a delusion, which we can trace to its source. From my earliest infancy, whenever a sensible effect has been produced in my nervous system, I have been accustomed to infer an external object. By asso ciation, perhaps also facilitated by evolution, the in ference has become so automatic as to be unnoticed. The consequence is, I think I am intuitively sensible of the external object when I am really inferring it. Nothing can prevent the delusion. I appear to see the paper and its distance from me. I cannot now consciously disengage the sensation of the sensible object from the inference of the perceptible original. Hence the limits of consciousness as an evidence. Consciousness does not become reflective, and therefore a source of psychology, till many operations have already become automatic in the conscious subject. The process from the sense of the insensible object to the inference of the perceptible original has been re peated an incalculable number of times before any man is sufficiently adult to consciously reflect on what he has been doing. Accordingly, consciousness is the source rather of the nature than of the origin of o knowledge ; invaluable for what we know now, delusive for how we came to know it. I am conscious that I somehow apprehend a sensible and an insensible world ; but I am not conscious of the exact point at 48 PHYSICAL REALISM TART i. which it ceases to be sensible, and becomes insensible and inferred. Intuitive realists were right in appealing to consciousness for the nature of knowledge ; only they should have appealed from the ordinary to the scientific consciousness. But they were quite wrong in appealing to consciousness for the ultimate origin of knowledge. They said truly, ' I apprehend an external world ' ; they said falsely, ' I apprehend it intuitively/ Nevertheless, the antithesis between the nature and origin of knowledge must not be exaggerated. Con sciousness tells us something of the origin of our know ledge. We are not conscious of the inferences of child- o hood : when we are old enough to take notice we become conscious of new inferences. We are not con scious of inferring an external world : we are conscious of inferring corpuscles. The exact limit is that we are not conscious of the primary data and the first inferences, but of adult inferences. But, again, con sciousness has something to tell us concerning even the primary data of sense. It is not their direct but their indirect evidence. It tells us what is our know ledge of objects, and this conscious knowledge must be explained by the primary data. Thus consciousness, on the whole, is the apprehension of our knowledge of objects and the test of the primary data and origin ; it is the direct evidence of the nature, the indirect evidence of the origin of knowledge. The facts of con sciousness must be first described and then explained by all scientific psychology. The main fact to be ex plained is our consciousness that we somehow appre hend a sensible and an insensible physical world. There is a superficiality of consciousness as there is of sensation. Yet each is the origin of a philosophy. Without sensation there would be no natural, without THAI', in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 40 consciousness no mental philosophy. Sensation is neces sary to the science of nature, consciousness to the science of in hid. Sensation apprehends what is sensible, consciousness what is knowledge. Sensation carries us some little distance into physical causation, conscious ness into the origin of knowledge. But sensation leaves us to infer causes essendi in external nature, conscious ness causce cognoscendi in internal knowledge. Yet sensation is the indirect test of all hypotheses to ex plain the causes of sensible objects, consciousness of all hypotheses to explain the origin of conscious know ledge. Nevertheless, both in themselves are superficial ; for sensation has no immediate intuition of the external causes of nature, and consciousness none of the internal data of knowledge. As direct evidence, sensation tells ns only the bare sensible effect and not its external causes, consciousness only what we know now, not how we came to know it. Sensation and consciousness are twT> senses, the outer and the inner. Neither is false ; both are limited. Truth is in pro/undo ; yet not in a bottomless abyss, but in depths to be plumbed only by reason, and that reason not a priori, but logical inference from the outer and inner senses. Not sensation, but reasoning from sensation, discovers external causes ; not consciousness, but reasoning from consciousness, discovers the primary data and origin of knowledge. Consciousness, then, does not aid the idealist in his assertion that all the immediate objects of sense are psychical. It tells us that we somehow know physical objects. It is so far in favour of realism. Having, however, inferred long ago from sensible data that- physical objects exist in the external world, we cannot now help seeming to be conscious of perceiving them intuitively. This confusion favours intuitive realism. E 50 PHYSICAL IlEALISM PART i. But consciousness cannot be used as direct evidence to tell us what we intuitively perceive, because our intui tions were overlaid with our inferences long before our consciousness became attentive. Moreover — and this is the main point — the confusion of what we intuitively perceive by our senses with what we mediately infer by our reason is cleared up by philosophy. What philo sophy ? This question brings us to the second kind of direct evidence for the data of sense. The philosophy which has distinguished the data of sense from their inferred causes is natural philosophy. Natural philosophy has shown that the sensible object is not really identical with, but is an effect distinct from, its external original. When a person hears a cannon fired at a considerable distance, his first impres sion is that he hears the sound at the very moment the ball issues from the cannon's mouth, and that the cannon sounds as he hears it. But if he ascends a hill, and the cannon again fires, he finds that he sees the smoke of the camion long before he hears the sound, and can count several seconds between the object seen and the object heard. There is only one possible explanation of this distinction. The object seen and the object heard are neither identical with one another, nor with the external object which produces them. The smoke ascends from the cannon and reflects the undulations of light, at the same moment as the ball leaves the camion and com municates vibrations to the air. But the undulations of light travel faster than the vibrations of air, and produce a visible effect on the person before the audible effect is produced by the slower mode of motion. The visible effect produced by the undulations is not the smoke, and the audible effect produced by the vibra tions is not the cannon's roar : else thev would be CHAP. III. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 51 apprehended at the same moment. Both are effects of, neither identical with, the external object. Again, natural philosophy in the department of physics has shown that external things do not in all their attributes precisely correspond to their effects on our senses. They have duration, extension and motion corresponding to their attributes as sensibly perceived ; but they have not heat or colour in the way in which we touch what is hot or see what is coloured. On the contrary, the causes of sensible heat and colour are in sensible motions. The attributes which are in nature as they are in our senses, are called primary; while those which are not in nature as they ara in our senses, are called secondary qualities. Again, natural philosophy has proved that external things affect our senses by the causation of motion. To begin with motion before it affects the senses ; either a given external thing may itself move from a distance, until it comes into contact with a sensitive subject, as a cannon-ball does when it hits a man ; or it propagates a motion from particle to particle until the particles im mediately in contact with the sensitive subject receive the motion, a process which takes place in the propaga tion of the undulations of light. In both cases the result is the same : the object immediately apprehended could not be the thing at a distance, but the thing immediately next to the sensitive organ. But we shall find that it is not even the nearest thing, as a matter of fact, but an effect within our senses. Again, biology, from Galen onwards, has shown that the nervous system is the material cause susceptible of the effect produced by the efficiency of the external object. It has discovered much of the structure of the nervous system. The peripheral terminations of nervous E 2 52 PHYSICAL HEALISM PAhT I. fibres are not actually exposed to external tilings. Hence the motion lias to be propagated through a non- sensitive covering before it is actually brought to the nerve. It is impossible, therefore, to be sensible of an external object, from which the nervous substance is divided by a medium in the body of the sentient being. Moreover, when the peripheral termination of a nervous fibre has been reached, the effect is still insensible till the motion has been communicated to the brain. When a nerve has been cut off from the brain, if the part between the peripheral termination and the section be irritated, no sensible effect takes place ; but if the part between the brain and the section be irritated by pres sure, or electricity, or disease, the effect is sensible. The brain, therefore, is an integral part of the nervous material susceptible of a sensible effect. I say a part, because there is no evidence that the brain alone would be sensitive, if a whole nervous structure up to the point at which it loses itself in the brain were removed. But the whole evidence together clearly shows that no sensible effect is produced by an external object until the propagation of motion from the external object has passed, not only the external medium, but what may be called the internal medium of the periphery, has reached the nervous fibres, and communicated itself to the brain. The nervous system is the primary matter susceptible of a sensible effect, and the sensible effect, therefore, is internal. It is further evident that, like other material causes, the nervous system partly determines the effect. It is susceptible of effects, like the primary qualities of ex ternal objects, but not like their secondary qualities. Probably its structure is adequate to the former, but not sufficiently subtle for the latter. Hence the dura- CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 53 tion, extension and motion of external bodies is able to produce similar sensible duration, extension and motion in the nervous system. But when the delicate vibrations of the air and the still more subtle undula tions of ajther strike upon the organs of hearing, touch and vision, the nervous structure of these organs is too coarse-grained to reproduce them, and substitutes the heterogeneous effect of sensible sound and the still more heterogeneous effects of sensible heat and light. Lastly, evolution has made it exceedingly probable that, like other material causes, the nervous system has itself been modified by the repeated action of the ex ternal efficient on its structure. It is probable that, by the frequent operation of appropriate stimuli on parti cular parts of the general sensitive system, the original sense of touch has been differentiated into the five senses. I would make two further suggestions. First, it is probable that as touch preceded the other senses, so the feelings preceded touch. In this case, the sentient being at first simply felt mere pleasure and pain from external objects; afterwards proceeded to the more complex operation of touch, in which the sensation of touching is distinct from the sensible object, hot or cold, in the tactile nerves, and the consciousness of touching distinct both from the sensation and the sensible object ; and, last of all, proceeded to infer external causes. Secondly, it is probable that, as the nervous system has become more differentiated, it may also become more subtle, and therefore more discriminative of secondary qualities. Some approach to this ideal may be found in sensible sound, in which there is some trace of vibrations, though not adequate to the external vibrations. Why, then, may not the nervous system some day become more PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. attuned to represent aethereal undulations to some extent in the wonderful sense of vision ? The discoveries of natural philosophy eliminate intuitive realism, by proving that the external is not identical with the sensible object, but is the cause which produces it in the nervous system. Contenting himself with crude consciousness and common sense, forgetting how late consciousness becomes reflective, and that common sense never becomes a science, the intuitive realist takes the appearance that we have an intuition of the external world for a fact, and some times even converts it into a first principle. But he comes into contradiction with science. Natural philo sophy shows that the external world affects us indi rectly, and that we have no empirical intuition except of ourselves. We might doubt between consciousness and science, if we could not see that the supposed in tuition of the external world is a delusion of association, and that consciousness is put out of court by its in ability to reflect at the time when the inference of the external world was being made ; made so often then as to have become automatic, and now made so quickly as to seem an intuition. On the strength of science, then, we must reject the hypothesis that the data of sense are to be found in the external world, in the non-ego. The same scientific discoveries raise a strong pre_ sumption in favour of physical realism, which simply adopts the scientific account without further hypo thesis. In the first place, I suppose that the effect produced on the nervous system is the sensible physical object, which we are conscious of apprehending, but by a confusion believe to be an object external to ourselves : for instance, when we see something white, it seems to CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 50 be the external paper, or what not, but it is really the effect produced by the paper reflecting undulations on the optic nerve. Secondly, I suppose that as we know the external physical cause to produce the sensible physical effect, and as we must start from sense, we must use the sensible physical object impressed on o in ner ves to infer the external physical object, as cause. The scientific account of the causation of the sensible effect leads directly to physical realism, which simply reads the process of causation backwards into a process of knowledge. o Biology has brought the sensible effect within the nervous system. Has it carried it further ? The attempt has often been made by biologists. They sup pose that the physical effect produced in the nervous system is not yet sensible, even when it has reached the brain ; that it remains a mere impression, no more sensible than the external object ; and that when the motion of the external object has produced the motion of the medium, the motion of the medium the motion of the nerves, the motion of the nerves the motion of the brain, the process is not yet finished. They suppose that the cerebral motion, which is physical, produces a sensation which is psychical ; and they do not ordi narily distinguish the sensible object from the sensation. From this hypothesis it would follow that the hot felt, the white seen, the sweet tasted, the durable, extended, and moving, apprehended by any sense are psychical affections produced by cerebral motion. The sensible object will be neither the external object nor the in ternal effect in the nervous system, but the internal psychical sensation. If so, realism will have to succumb to idealism. The question we now have to ask ourselves is not PHYSICAL REALISM TART I. whether the external object causes our sensation in some way or other. The scientific evidence of the propa gation of motion from external objects to our bodies and the conscious involuntariness of sensation are suffi cient proofs that the external object does cause our sensation. It is, however, a different question how one causes the other. Secondly, the question we now have to ask ourselves is not whether there is any evidence at all that the sensation produced is purely psychical. What is to be said on this point will follow when we come to the Cartesian philosophy in detail. The present questions are, first, whether biology proves that within ourselves nervous and cerebral motion produces a psychical sensation ; secondly, if so, whether it follows that the sensible object also becomes a psychical sensa- The answer is that biologists have gone beyond biology, and that no affirmative answer can be ^iven to these questions from the observations, or direct in ferences from sense, which are the evidences of their science. In the first place, the nervous system is imperfectly known. It is quite clear that external objects propa- ate motions to the nerves, but it is not at all clear what happens when the effect has been produced. In optics, for example, so long as we are reading of the undulations of light, of the manner in which rays are communicated to the eye, of the structure of the lens by which the rays are made to converge on the retina and of the general structure of the retina, and even of nervous elements, everything is clear. But the further we penetrate from the retina along the optic nerve to the optic centres at the base of the brain, the darker the subject becomes, and fact seems to pass into hypothesis. It is the same witli all our senses CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 57 difficulties begin at the very terminations of the nerves. What, for example, are the precise functions of the tactile corpuscles, of the rods and cones of the retina, of the rods of Corti in the ear ? We know more of nervous structure than of nervous action. What is nervous action ? This is an unsolved problem. What is cerebral action ? This is a more unsolved problem. The structural connections of afferent nerves with centres, of centres with efferent nerves, of efferent nerves with muscles, and to some extent the structural constituents of nerves and muscles are fairly made out. It is also found that an appre ciable interval takes place between the stimulation of an afferent nerve and the muscular motion which it indirectly but ultimately produces. This interval proves an important point about nervous action ; it is a motion because it takes time to go from place to place. The genus of nervous action, then, is known to be mo tion. But what is its differentia ? After the first crude hypothesis of animal spirits moving in the nerves, nervous motion was supposed to be the simplest form of me chanical motion by impact, as if the impression were pushed along to the brain, as a series of bricks knock one another over. Then it was supposed to be vibra tion. Later researches tend to show that it has relations to the motions of electricity and of chemical action. It is, no doubt, some molecular motion allied to other motions of the same kind ; but its peculiarity is its slowness, compared, for instance, with electricity. Its precise differentia is at present unknown. Cerebral motion is still more unknown. It has been found, by experimenting on various parts of the brain, that different parts are to some extent connected with different muscular motions, from which it is inferred 58 rriYSiCAL REALISM TART I. that they are also connected with different nervous motions. But how the brain moves between the stimu lus of an afferent nerve and its effect on an efferent nerve is unknown. He would be a bold man who would come forward and say he knows the motion by which the effect impressed on the nerves is communi cated to the brain and there made ready for sensation. How, then, can he say he knows that cerebral motion, of which in biology he is ignorant, produces a psychi cal sensation, which is beyond the venue of a physical science ? . Secondly, the so-called transmutation of cerebral motion into psychical sensation is admitted to be per formed in some mysterious way, unknown and inex plicable. This point may be made clear by the following quotation from Professor Huxley's Lay Sermon on Des cartes' Discourse, in which the Professor is trying to prove that thought is existence, and, so far as we are concerned, existence is thought :— ' For example, I take up a marble, and I find it to be a red, round, hard, single body. We call the redness, the roundness, the hardness, and the singleness, " quali ties " of the marble ; and it sounds, at first, the height of absurdity to say that all these qualities are modes of our own consciousness, which cannot even be conceived to exist in the marble. But consider the redness to begin with ; how does the sensation of redness arise ? The waves of a certain very attenuated matter, particles of which are vibrating with vast rapidity, but with very different velocities, strike upon the marble, and those which vibrate with a particular velocity are thrown off from its surface in all directions. The optical appa ratus of the eye gathers some of these together, and gives them such a course that they impinge upon the CHAP. III. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 59 surface of the retina, which is a singularly delicate apparatus, connected with the termination of the fibres of the optic nerve. The impulses of the attenuated matter, or aether, affect this apparatus and the fibres of the optic nerve in a certain way, and the change in the fibres of the optic nerve produces yet other changes in the brain ; and these, in some fashion unknown to us, give rise to the feeling, or consciousness, of redness. If the marble could remain unchanged, and either the rate of vibration of the aether, or the nature of the retina could be altered, the marble would seem not red, but some other colour. There are many people who are what are called colour-blind, being unable to distin guish one colour from another. Such an one might declare our marble to be green, and he would be quite as right in saying that it is green as we are in declaring it to be red. But, then, as the marble cannot, in itself, be both green and red at the same time, this shows that the quality " redness " must be in our consciousness, and not in the marble.' Thirdly, the hypothesis of this unknown transmuta tion is inconsistent with one of the best established facts of the nervous system— its physical continuity. It supposes that physical motion of afferent nerves and brain causes psychical .sensation, which causes psy chical volition, which causes physical motion of efferent nerves, which causes physical motion of muscles. But wherever nervous structure is accessible to observation, the afferent nerves finally communicate with centres which communicate with efferent nerves, without any rupture of physical continuity. It might, indeed, be urged that the intermediate purely psychical processes nevertheless intervene insensibly in the centre between the afferent and efferent nervous processes. But this 00 PHYSICAL REALISM TAUT i. hypothesis is rendered most difficult by the phenomena of reflex action. In reflex action, the afferent and efferent nervous processes are certainly connected with out any breach of physical continuity. It might again be objected that only the nerves of reflex processes are continuous. But we cannot divide the nerves of reflex action from those of conscious action, and say that the former nerves are physically continuous, whereas the latter are interrupted by purely psychical sensations and volitions, because the very same nerves, which are used in conscious, are used also in reflex actions. For example, we may wink either voluntarily or automati cally. An object strikes the eye, transmits its motion to the afferent optic nerve, which communicates with the brain, which transmits the motion to the efferent facial nerve, governing the orbicular muscle of the eyelids, which makes them close. The whole of this process often takes place automatically, without any rupture of phy sical continuity. When it takes place consciously, are we to say that the physical motion, having arrived from the optic nerve to the brain, does not produce the motion of the efferent nerve, but produces a psychical sensation instead, which produces a psychical volition, which at length affects the efferent nerve? There is not a tittle, of biological or any other evidence that the physical continuity is sometimes preserved sometimes broken in this manner in the very same series of nerves. To escape this gratuitous hypothesis of psychical interruption, some of the mental physiologists resort to paradoxes, in order at once to preserve the physical continuity of the nervous system, together with purely psychical sensations. Allowing that in all cases the motion of the afferent nerves propagated through the centres produces the motion of the efferent nerves in a CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE Gl continuous manner, some suppose that, standing quite apart from these physical processes, the conscious sub ject is a sort of impartial spectator, performing purely psychical operations that have no physical effects, while others positively go the length of supposing that not only in sentient beings, but in all nature, there are always two independent but parallel streams, the well- known physical motions and supposititious psychical processes accompanying them. These hypotheses are exceedingly like the Pre-established Harmony, and like it in being made to get over a self-made difficulty. They are hypotheses to cover an hypothesis. The former alternative does not go beyond conscious beings, but it fails to explain a fact of consciousness far more certain than the hypothesis. We are certainly con scious that external objects somehow affect our feelings and sensations, that our sensations, desires and infer ences affect our volitions, that our volitions somehow affect the motions of our bodies. It is absurd to suppose that our conscious operations are inert and idle, when they are consciously both passive and active, and that the conscious subject is like a child, given his opera tions like a toy to make believe he is very busy, but really to keep him quiet. The latter alternative which carries this inert psychism into everything whatsoever, without any evidence, except the original hypothesis of two parallel streams in a sentient being, would have us believe that the wind blows, the waves swell, the earth moves, with some obscure sentience. Such a per sonification of nature was excusable in primitive religion, but it is not worthy of modern science. Lastly, to return to the usual hypothesis that nervous motion produces psychical sensation, which again issues in nervous motion, one cannot help asking what can be 02 PHYSICAL REALISM TART T. the source of a biological hypothesis so foreign, nay, so contradictory to the evidence of biology ? Biologists have become psychologists, and have fallen under the dominion of the idealists. Without any criticism, with out any biological proof, simply because it is the fashion, and as if it were a first principle, they have accepted the idealistic hypothesis of purely psychical sensation, and thereon have reared an hypothesis of their own, that nervous motion produces this psychical sensation, which reproduces nervous motion. Now, the present question, as I said before, is not whether there is a purely psychical sensation, but whether there is any evidence that motion propa gated from the afferent nerves to the brain produces such a tertium quid, instead of producing motion from the brain to the efferent nerves. There is no evidence, either psychological or biological. As a psychologist, I am conscious that I perform the opera tion of sensation, which for argument's sake may be assumed as purely psychical ; but I am not conscious of my nervous motion. I am not, therefore, conscious of sensation arising out of nervous motion. A biologist, not in himself but in another body, can observe a nervous system, its physical continuity, and the time of its action proving motion ; but this dissector cannot either observe or be conscious of the sensation of another nervous system ; he cannot, therefore, observe nervous motion issuing in sensation. That there is such a pro cess from the physical into the psychical and back is sheer hypothesis, an arbitrary concordance of idealism and biology, Nor is this all ; they proceed to suppose that the effect produced by the external object on the internal nervous system is not yet sensible, but that, when the Tin-; PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 03 psychical sensation is produced, the effect for the first time becomes sensible, so that the sensible object is either identical with the sensation, or at all events is equally psychical. But, in the first place, even if a purely psychical sensation is produced in this manner, it does not follow that the sensible object becomes , psychical. There is no reason, except the /old and ex ploded hypothesis similia similibus cognoscuntur, why a psychical operation may not apprehend a physical object. Secondly, whatever may be the nature of the operation, it is most improbable in itself that the hot felt through one's body, the white seen through one's eyes, the loud heard through one's ears, is anything but a physical condition of the tactile, optic and auditory nerves in connection with the brain. The idealistic hypothesis of psychical sensation, then, does not prove the biological hypothesis of the transmutation of nervous motion into psychical sensation, nor either hypothesis the third hypothesis that the sensible object is psychical. Ter sunt conati imponere Pelio Ossam Scilicet atque Ossse frondosum involvere Olympum. The study of the mental physiology of the present day suggests several reflections. In the first place, the insensible and imperceptible motions of asther, their reflections from other bodies, and their impact on the senses are now well-established discoveries of science. They are known qualities, which are not sensations, but the insensible causes of sensations. Not all knowable qualities, therefore, are sensations. Secondly, as we recede from the external world behind the periphery into the nervous system, science becomes more vague. What are nervous and cerebral motions ? Thirdly, we are told that cerebral motion, which is physical, pro duces a heterogeneous sensation, which is psychical. 64 PHYSICAL IIKALISM PART i. But we are given no evidence of this transmutation. We cannot observe it in a dissecting-room. If it be said we are conscious of it, we answer that we are conscious of sensation, but not of cerebral motion, and therefore not of cerebral motion producing psychical sensation as a separate and indeed heterogeneous fact. Fourthly, this transmutation of one unknown into another unknown is admitted to take place in an unknown manner. Fifthly, we are illogically asked to infer from this trans mutation of cerebral motion into psychical sensation that the sensible object, e.g. the red seen in vision, is also a psychical sensation. Sixthly, we are not told how, if the object of sense thus becomes psychical, we infer the external causes, which, as we have seen, are much the clearest part of the whole business. Seventhly, we often find that, with more logic than consistency, the external objects which were previously made the scientific causes of sensation are nevertheless afterwards declared unknown and unknowable. Meanwhile, the fallacy of this so-called biology is its assumption of psychological idealism. All that is really proved by natural philosophy is that external redness, for example, is an insensible quality of insensible aether, consisting of a vibration of a certain velocity ; and that, reflected by an external object, it produces in the optic nerves of a sentient being a sensible redness, which is not iden tical with the external vibrations nor itself a sensible vibration at all. The simple conclusion from these scientific facts would be that the nervous effect is the sensible redness, from which, together with sensible motion, the external motions of vibration are inferred. Nothing more is proved by mental physiology. When we look back at the whole light thrown by natural philosophy on the sensible object, we shall find CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 65 that it is known that external physical objects produce internal physical effects in the nervous system, but it is not known that these internal physical effects in their turn produce an internal psychical object of sense. Meanwhile, we are conscious that, when we use our senses, we somehow apprehend a physical object, which seems by an illusion to be also external. The simplest hypothesis, which can be made in these circumstances, is that the sensible object is neither external on the one hand nor psychical on the other, but the internal physical effect on the nervous system. In other words, there is a via media between intuitive realism and idealism of all kinds, closer to the scientific facts than either hypothesis ; namely, physical realism. At the same time, scientific observation is not a positive proof of physical realism. It brings the sensible object within the man : it cannot decide whether it is or is not within the soul. Its ultimate result is that the sensible object is not external but internal, not without but within the sentient being, not identical with the physical object in the outside world but produced in the interior microcosm of the animal organism. This negative conclusion eliminates intuitive, but it does not o positively establish physical realism. As a direct evidence, natural philosophy, being founded on obser vation, is able to show that the sensible object is not the physical object outside, but is within the nervous system ; not being founded on consciousness, it is not able to decide whether this internal sensible object is physical or psychical, whether it is the nervous effect, or something even more internal. It leaves this problem unsolved. Accordingly, there still remain two pos sible alternatives — physical realism and psychological idealism. F GO PHYSICAL REALISM TART i. Nevertheless, scientific observation makes physical realism the more probable alternative, because this hypothesis simply accepts the proved nervous effect as the sensible object, instead of hypothesising a further psychical object, which is unproved, and breaks the nervous continuity. When as a mental philosopher one adds consciousness to scientific observation, the proba bility of physical realism is increased. Consciousness tells us that we somehow apprehend physical objects, which appear also to be sensibly external. Scientific observation disabuses us of the appearance that the sensible object is external, but not of the consciousness that it is physical. Natural philosophy, as a direct evidence, may be said to remove the physical object of sense from the external to the internal world, but no further than the nervous system. The most probable mental philosophy would simply conclude that it there becomes sensible — though only the most probable. We asked for direct evidence that the immediate object, hot, coloured, &c., perceived by our senses is a psychical phenomenon, and we find there is none. Con sciousness is so far from saying so, that it confuses the immediate and the mediate, and leads us to think that the immediate object is not only physical but external. Scientific analysis corrects this confusion, and teaches us that the immediate object is not external but internal, but does not go on to show that it is not only internal but psychical. I suspect that the idealists by a kind of confusion have changed the truth that the object of sense is not external but internal into the hypothesis that it is not physical but psychical. The idealist may reply that direct evidence is not required for an hypothesis, and that the psychical object is like ether — something inaccessible to direct evidence, CHAT. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 67 but needed to explain the facts. I accept this issue.' I admit that, if the idealistic hypothesis of the sensible object could explain the facts of the known world and eliminate the hypothesis of physical realism, it would be proved by this indirect evidence. There would still be no direct evidence that a hot or coloured object is not a physical but a psychical fact. But, contrary to all ap pearance, we should be obliged to conclude that, as light is paradoxically but really an undulation of aether, so is the seen, or felt, or heard, or tasted, or smelt, a psychical, and not a physical, fact. The gist of the idealistic hypothesis is that not some but all the immediate objects are psychical, and that no physical object whatever is apprehended by sense. The consequence is that all our sensitive experience will be limited to psychical objects; for, so far as it is sensitive, experience is merely the sum of our sen sations. Moreover, the supposition of a priori elements of knowledge will not help us, for nobody pretends that we have an a priori apprehension of the physical to add to an a posteriori apprehension of the psychical : such an hypothesis would be too great an inversion. The consequence is that all the data of our knowledge will be psychical. No doubt different idealists will pro vide more or less of such psychical data. Some will have merely psychical sensations, others will add a psychical subject, and others again psychical apprehen sions a priori. But at the widest the data will all be psychical facts of some kind or other. Now the question arises, what can be known from psychical data? If all the immediate objects I touch, see, taste, smell, and hear are psychical, and I am psychi cal, and all my apprehensions are psychical, if all my sensitive experience is of nothing but psychical phocno- F 2 GS PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. inena, if all the data which form the immediate premises of my mediate knowledge are psychical, what can I infer from such facts in the premises ? To answer this question we must consult the logical rules of inference. All inference is by similarity. Not to enter into the question whether there is one fundamental type, there are three apparent kinds of inference — induction, deduc tion, and analogical inference. All these are different modes of reasoning from similar to similar. In induction we apprehend that similar particulars have a similar characteristic, and infer that the class, including those and all other particulars similar to them, have that similar characteristic. In deduction we start with a proposition stating the similar characteristics of a class, either inferred by induction or otherwise known, as major premise ; we combine it with a minor premise, asserting that something is one of the class of similar particulars ; and from this combination we infer that this new but similar particular has the similar characteristic already known to belong to the class. In analogical in ference, which is an imperfect substitute for induction followed by deduction, we apprehend that a particular has a characteristic, or several similar particulars have a similar characteristic; we apprehend by analogy that another particular is similar to the given parti cular or similar particulars ; and from the analogy we infer that this new but similar particular may have the characteristic similar to that of the given particular or particulars. Various men are mortal, . • . all men are mortal : all men are mortal, I am a man, . • . I am mortal : the earth is inhabited, Mars is like the earth, . Mars may be inhabited : — these inductions, deductions, and analogical inferences are nothing but inferences from similar to similar. They are founded CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE GO also on the reality and knowledge of classes and laws. But what is a class except similar things, and what is a law except the fact that similar things possess similar characteristics ? From this limitation of inference to similarity it follows that whatever the character of the data, such will be that which is inferred. If all the data were psychical, then, by parity of reasoning, we could only infer the psychical. If we never had direct experience of anything physical whatever, then, there being nothing physical in the premises, nothing physical in the con clusion could possibly be inferred. From the similar the similar is inferred ; from the psychical the psychical. But in order to infer the physical we must have some physical data. The universal similarity between the data in the premises and the inferred in the conclusion requires to be guarded from misapprehension. I said above that the old hypothesis— like is known by like — is a fallacy. I now say that like is known from like. These positions are not inconsistent. The former refers to the relation of subject and object, the latter to the relation of object to object. There is no reason why the object appre hended should be like the subject apprehending ; but there are reasons why objects inferred should be like the objects from which they are inferred— the rules of logic. If the subject has constantly had physical objects pre sented to it, it must apprehend them, or be useless. But when the subject has before it the immediate objects which can be presented to it, whether a posteriori or a priori, it has all the data from which reasoning can start ; and if that reasoning is to maintain the consistency of truth, it can add nothing in the conclusion which is not justified by the presence of something similar in the 70 PHYSICAL 11EALISM PART I. premises. If reasoning contains, on the Kantian hypo thesis, a priori apprehensions, these will be part of the data ; but if it adds anything, not in the data but in the conclusion, which has no analogue in the premises, reasoning becomes paralogism. This fallacy is well known in deduction ; but it is equally true of induction, which only generalises the subjects and predicates con tained in the particular instances, and of analogical idference, which infers that one particular similar to another may be similar also in a characteristic already apprehended in that other. Therefore, although like objects are not necessarily immediately apprehended by a like subject, only like objects are inferred from like objects, not by any necessity in the relation of subject and object, but by the nature of reasoning. Hence a psychical subject may immediately perceive physical objects ; but if it were a psychical subject and perceived psychical objects it could infer nothing but psychical things, similar either to the psychical subject perceiving or to the psychical objects perceived. Again, the logical canon, like is known from like, must not be confused with the metaphysical hypothesis, like causes have like effects. Aristotle extended the principle of the propagation of the species from the organic to the inorganic world, and thought that every cause is homogeneous with its effect. Modern science has discountenanced this view, except in the far-off sense that all physical causation may be the propagation of motion in various forms. But when I say that we can only infer like objects, what I mean is not that we must infer causes like the effects, but causes like the causes which we have already known. For example, Newton, already knowing the effects requiring gravitation to cause them in terrestrial bodies, when he found similar CHAP. irr. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 71 effects in celestial bodies, inferred that their cause also is a celestial, similar to terrestrial, gravitation. Now, if all the data of sense \vere psychical, not only the effects but also the causes in sense would be psychical : conse quently, when we came to a sensible effect, similar to other sensible effects, but not due to any sensible cause, we should have to infer a similar cause beyond sense ; and, as all the causes in sense w^ould ex hypothesi be psychical, we should have to infer, by parity of rea soning, a psychical cause, not because the effect was psychical, but because all previously known causes would be psychical. If, on the other hand, there were physical causes in the data of sense, we could then, and only then, infer a similar physical cause beyond sense. Again, when I say that only like objects are inferred from like, I do not mean that nothing new can be inferred, but only nothing new which is not similar to the data. The conclusion is no mere restatement of the premises. What is inferred need not have been already experi enced, nor is reasoning confined to merely reproducing the immediate data of the senses. But what is inferred must be similar to what has already been experienced. What is new, and has never been, nor ever will be, in experience, such as an ^ethereal undulation, can be in ferred. But the ethereal undulation is a motion similar to the experienced motion of waves of water. Nothing new, which is not similar to the data, can be inferred. It is true of the Deity Himself, who, though not experi enced, is inferred to be like man, but infinitely intensi fied in the attributes which we already know in our selves. Consequently, if all the data were psychical, we should be able to draw inferences to similarly psychical subjects and similarly psychical objects, new but similar to the data. But we should not be able to infer some- 72 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. thing wholly new, dissimilar and heterogeneous, for which there was no analogue either in the sentient sub ject or in the sensible objects. Hence, the physical, for which there would be ex hypotliesi no analogue in the premises, could not be inferred. If, on the other hand, as I suppose, the sensible data are physical facts in my organism, I can then infer new but similar physical objects outside, although I have never immediately per ceived them by sense. Another misapprehension will immediately arise. It is said that one opposite implies another, and, therefore, though we experience only one opposite, we infer the other. Thus, it is supposed, from psychical data we infer their opposites, physical things. I am almost ashamed to write down Aristotle's distinction of con tradictories and contraries ; but it is necessary in an illogical age. Contradictory opposites are the positive and its negative, as relative and not relative, finite and not finite. Contrary opposites are the furthest removed positives, as white and black. Now contradictory op posites in a sense imply one another, but contrary opposites do not. White implies not white : it does not imply black. We might have apprehended white without having any conception of black, much less having proof of its existence. Secondly, great harm is done by such vague terms as ' imply ' and ' implication,' which some times mean conceiving and sometimes inferring. The positive, when apprehended, makes us conceive the con tradictory negative, but does not make us infer that it exists. Are we to fall into the old sophism of arguing that as something is contradicted by nothing, nothin^ o «7 O" O exists ? It is a common argument that the relative which we experience implies the non-relative and absolute, CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE To the finite implies the infinite. This is an utter confu sion of contradictories and contraries. The relative im plies the not relative ; but the contradictory, not relative, is not necessarily the positive contrary, abso lute, for it also includes nothing ; and the relative, in implying the not relative, does not decide whether it is absolute or nothing. As white implies not white, but not necessarily black or any other particular colour, so the relative implies not relative, but not necessarily the particular species of not relative, absolute. The same remark applies to the opposition of finite and infinite, except that in this case the term ' infinite ' is ambiguous, being properly the not finite, but including both that which is not finite, because it is nothing, and that which is not finite, because it extends without limit. The finite implies its contradictory, not its contrary : it implies the negative not finite, but does not imply the particular positive species, the infinite which extends without limit. Secondly, the relative and finite imply only in the sense of making us conceive the mere contradictories, not relative and not finite. The positive sides of the contradictions not only leave the content of the negatives undetermined, but also leave the question undecided whether we can infer that there is anything corresponding to the ideas of the negatives. Nor do they even give us the ideas till we have not only apprehended the positives, but also apprehended that they are relative and finite. The relative and the finite, then, when apprehended to be such, make us conceive the ideas of the not relative and not finite, but give us no idea of a positive some thing absolute and extending without limits, much less make us infer that this species of not relative and not finite is something real as distinguished from nothing 74 PHYSICAL TIEALISM at all. When we merely experience something which happens to be finite, we need not think of any opposite ; if we think of it as finite, we must have an idea of the not finite ; but we need not form an idea of the positive infinite, much less can we prove that there is something infinite, and say, ' I experience the finite and relative, therefore there is an infinite and absolute.' Men accept such arguments because they think it helps to prove the existence of a Deity. But the finite and relative do not make us conceive a positive infinite absolute, much less infer its existence ; and theology has better argu ments for a Deity than the confusion of negative and positive, of contradictory and contrary opposition, of conception and inference, of ideas and judgments. Similarly, the psychical does not imply the physical. The physical and the psychical are contraries, not con tradictories. The contradictory of the psychical is the not psychical, which may be anything else or nothing. Suppose that I had experienced nothing but psychical data. If I had never thought of them as psychical, but only as hot, red, and so on, I should have had no reason to conceive the not psychical. If I had thought of them as psychical, I must then have had the bare idea of not psychical as its contradictory. But I should neither have been able to have inferred that it existed nor what it was. The content of the idea would have been the bare negation or contradictory of the psychical. I should have had no idea of the physical as a positive contrary, much less have proved its existence. Just as the apprehension of white makes me conceive the idea of not white, but does not infer that there is any other colour, much less the contrary black, and just as the apprehension of the relative and finite makes me con ceive the idea of not relative and not finite, but does not CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 75 infer that there is anything which is not relative and not finite, much less the contrary absolute and extending without limits, so the apprehension of the psychical would make me conceive the idea of not psychical, but would not tell me that there is anything positive which is not psychical, much less that it is the contrary, physical. To infer the existence of the positive con trary, the physical, I should have required other than psychical data, which would, however, have been ex hypotliesi all the data possible. In all cases the existence of a contrary is a matter not of implication in the knowledge of the opposite con trary, but a matter of independent inference. Human reasoning would indeed be easy, if without further question the moment one had ascertained a thing, one knew that its contrary existed ; when one had experi enced white, one knew black ; when all experience had been of the relative and finite, one knew the absolute and infinite ; when all the immediate data of all reason ing were psychical, one straightway knew that there are physical things. Why, one contrary does not even make us conceive the idea of another, much less infer its existence. The white makes us conceive the idea, not white : we want other evidence to infer the existence of the black. The psychical makes us conceive the idea,' not psychical : we want other evidence to prove the existence of the physical. A synthesis from psychical data to physical things must be founded on some better device than the fallacy of the implication of opposites. But in reality the whole hypothesis of such a synthesis is illogical. To infer physical things we require more than psychical data, and their implications, and their consequences : we require physical data in the premises similar to the physical objects in the conclusion. 7G PHYSICAL REALISM TART i. The canons of inference, then, teach us, first, that from similars similars are inferred ; secondly, that what is inferred may be something new so long as it is similar to some of the data ; and thirdly, that it cannot be the contrary of all the data. Therefore, on the idealistic hypothesis that all the data are psychical, in the first place, what is inferred would also be psychical ; secondly, it would include other psychical subjects and other psy chical objects similar to those which ex Jiypotliesi form the data of inference ; but, thirdly, it would not include physical things, for which there would be no analogy, and which are not implied in merely psychical data : for psychical data would not make us even conceive, much less infer their contraries, physical things. On the other hand, if some of the data are physical, what is inferred can be physical like the data, different yet similar objects, the data being in our own bodies, the inferred objects in the external world. We constantly hear at the present day of two worlds and their correspondence — the psychical and the physical. It is not the purpose of this essay to deny this anti thesis, nor to depend upon it. But it is also commonly supposed that all the data of our knowledge belong to the former world, from which the latter is inferred. Against this hypothesis I direct this essay. If all the data of sense were psychical, the parity of reasoning would have no data to infer the physical. But the physical world is the object of natural science, which is knowledge. Therefore, not all the data of sense are psychical. There must be similar physical data to infer similar physical objects. Such, then, are the data required by the rules of reasoning to infer a physical world. We began by saying that, if the idealistic hypothesis led to the CHAP. TIT. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 77 only possible explanation of the facts, we must accept it even on this indirect evidence. We now see to what it logically leads. All that is inferred as well as all that is perceived, all that is immediate and all that is mediate, all that is apprehended in us and all that is known beyond, will be psychical. That is, all known realities will be psychical facts of some kind or another. As Berkeley says, the whole known world will be mind and ideas ; with Hegel, thought will be being and being will be thought. These are the logical idealisms. Nothing physical, and not psychical, will be inferrible, still less knowable. This logical consequence of all psychological idealism must be confronted with the discoveries of natural philo sophy. A survey of these discoveries shows an enormous mass of insensible and inconceivable realities, which are scientifically known by inference from sensible data. But they are physical realities, incapable of being re solved into any kind of psychical fact ; being insen sible they are not sensations, being inconceivable they are not ideas. It follows, therefore, that some things physical, and not psychical, are knowable, and not all known objects are psychical. The physical objects of scientific knowledge directly eliminate pure idealism. Starting synthetically from the common idealistic hypothesis that the sensible data are psychical, the pure idealist draws the strictly logical conclusion that all known objects, inferred from these psychical data of sense, must also be psychical. Accord ing to him, then, there are no physical objects of know ledge. His logic is consistent, but his conclusion is false. He has omitted the physical world which, being beyond our sensations and ideas, cannot be resolved into sensations or ideas, but which yet is an object of 78 PHYSICAL HKALISM TART r. 8(.ience_the most perfect form of knowledge. Not all known objects, therefore, are psychical; some are phy sical. Pure idealism then is false, and some form of realism true. As intuitive realism has already been eliminated by natural philosophy, it only remains to decide between the hypothetical realism of the cos- mothetic idealist and the physical realism of this essay. The physical objects of scientific knowledge in directly eliminate cosmothetic idealism with its hypo thetical realism. The cosmothetic idealist tries to reconcile the idealistic theory, that the sensible data are psychical, with the realistic theory that some objects knowable by inference from these data are physical. We have found that the realistic part of his theory is correct. He has the merit of admitting that there are physical objects of knowledge : this is his superiority to the pure idealist. He has the merit of admitting that they are not intuitively perceived by sense, but inferred : this is his superiority to the intuitive realist. But he is illogical. His defect is the inconsequence of supposing that physical objects, though not intuitively perceived, could be inferred from purely psychical data. But we have seen that all inference is by similarity, and there fore physical objects could not be inferred from purely psychical data. The physical would be the object of a new term in the conclusion, absent and un justified in the premises. If all the data of sense were psychical, then, by parity of reasoning, all objects knowable from them would be psychical. But by the discoveries of science, and by the admission of the cosmothetic idealist, some objects knowable by inference from the data of sense are physical. Therefore not all the data of sense are psychical. Sublata consequent tullitur antecedens. CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 79 Cosmotlietic and pure idealism are mutually destruc tive of each other. The former admits that some objects are physical, which prove that the latter is wrong in supposing all objects to be psychical. The latter admits that only psychical objects can be inferred from psychi cal data, so that the former is wrong in supposing that physical objects are inferred from psychical data. Pure idealism fails to recognise, cosmothetic idealism fails to explain, the knowledge of an insensible and inconceiv able physical world. If we combine both we destroy the common data of both. As the pure idealist says, if all the data were psychical all the objects would be psychical ; but as the cosmothetic idealist admits, not all the objects are psychical. It follows that both are wrong in saying all the data are psychical. Their data fail to explain the physical objects of scientific know ledge. Science eliminates all psychological idealism. Meanwhile the physical objects of scientific know ledge are not merely destructive of psychological idealism, but are also constructive of physical realism. They prove in themselves that some objects of know ledge are physical, and, in combination with the logical rules of inference, that some data of sense must be physical, to infer them. Similars are inferrible only from similars. Therefore the physical is inferrible only from the physical. But some objects of science are physical ; therefore they are inferrible only from physi cal data. These data of sense, however, though physical, are proved by scientific analysis to be internal ; there fore the data of sense are physical objects within our nervous system, from which we infer physical objects in the external world. This is the theory of physical realism, established by the logical rules of hypothesis. I admit that the direct evidences are not a positive 80 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. proof of physical realism. Consciousness, alone, is even in favour of intuitive realism. But scientific analysis destroys this hypothesis by separating the sensible effect from the external cause, and showing that the sensible object must be internal. On the other hand, it does not show that the sensible object is not only in ternal but psychical, and therefore does not favour idealism. It makes the intermediate theory of physical realism possible, even probable. I do not believe, how ever, that the data of sense are recoverable by any direct method, because from our very birth, and with inherited power, we overlay them with inferences. Hence the shipwreck of modern philosophy, which sup poses its hypotheses of sensible data to be first principles, and has alternated between the opposite but equally futile attempts to grasp physical things by sense, or to leap from psychical data to physical things. I admit, therefore, that the crucial evidence must be indirect. That hypothesis of the data of sense must be accepted, which explains the knowledge of the objects of science. This insensible, this inconceivable, this physical world of science is not an object of intuition, is not a sum of psychical sensations and ideas, is not inferrible from psychical sensations and ideas. Its knowledge then must be accounted for otherwise. It is inferrible from internal and physical data, the nervous system sensibly affected by external objects. The data of sense, then, are neither physical objects without, which are the causes not the objects of sense ; nor psychical objects within, from which nothing physica could be inferred ; but physical objects within, from which physical objects without are inferred by all, and known by science. Physical realism, therefore, or the theory of internal physical data to infer external physi- CHAP. in. THE PHYSICAL DATA OF SENSE 81 cal objects, is, in accordance with the logic of explana. tion and elimination, the only hypothesis of the data of sense sufficient to explain the knowledge of the objects of science. It is a mental philosophy born of natural philosophy, ' that great mother of sciences.' ' 1 Bacon, Nov. Org. i, 80. 82 PHYSICAL REALISM rAiir r. CHAPTER IV. THE HISTORICAL OKIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM. tr ABISTOTLK remarks that we ought not only to criticise our opponents, but also to point out the causes of their errors. The origin of intuitive realism and its presen- tative theory of perception, is the inevitable tendency of ordinary man to confound sense with reason, and his sensations with his inferences. He has so long been accustomed to infer an external world, that at last he cannot but fancy his senses perceive it. He seems to himself even to be conscious that it is so, calls his con fusion common sense, and at last defies philosophers to distinguish the sensible and the real. To have dis abused philosophy of this confusion is one of the many services owed by mankind to Greek philosophers. The distinction of sense and reason soon dawned on the Greeks, and with it the discovery that the object of sense is not the external thing at a distance from our selves, but some sort of result on our senses, from which the external tiling is inferred by reason. In short, the Greek philosophers founded the representa tire theory of sensitive perception. But they did not agree about the nature of the sensible object, or repre sentative of the external thing impressed on the senses. Without pretending to give a history of their views, we may distinguish two great epochs : the first, that in which the sensible object was regarded as a corporeal CHAP. iv. OlilGIN OF I'SYCJIOLOGICAL IDEALISM effect ; the second, that in which it began to be regarded as an incorporeal essence in our senses. In this second epoch the Greeks prepared the way for the theory that the sensible object is an incorporeal idea. But they never actually reached the idealistic theory. The first approach to a scientific theory of the objects of knowledge is to be found in the Atomists, Leucippus and Democritus of Abdera, the pioneers of a sound philosophy of nature. To them we owe the dawn of the truth, afterwards developed into the dis tinction of primary and secondary qualities, that the real and original qualities of particles are figure, position and arrangement, whose different combinations, together with motion, give rise to qualities, such as heat and colour, which, though really derivative, appear equally original to our senses. The manner, however, in which this important doc trine was presented to the world was not purely unex ceptionable. The Atomists, it is true, admitted that there is for every variety of sensible quality a distinct mode, or schema in their language, of the original qua lities ; for example, a sharp taste arises from angular, a sweet from round schemata. But, to say nothing of their crude speculations on corpuscular structure and motion, they fell into the fallacy of confusing the deri vative quality with its sensible effect in the famous dictum, ' Conventionally there is sweet, conventionally bitter, conventionally hot, conventionally cold, conven tionally colour ; but really atoms and void.' * From this Atomistic identification of secondary qualities with their sensible effects, assisted by the Heraclitean identity of contraries, it was but a short step to the sceptical theory of Protagoras, that all qualities are merely the 1 Scxt. Einp. Adv. Math. vii. 135. G 2 84 PHYSICAL REALISM TART i. appearances in our senses, without any correspondents in the fluent matter of nature. The Atomists did not recognise sufficiently, the Sceptics not at all, the fact that derivative or secondary qualities are qualities of external things. There is also a common tendency in modern mental philo sophy to identify secondary qualities with their sen sible manifestations. But for every sensible quality, which is the product of an external object, there is a distinct quality in the external object. A primary quality is also like the sensible quality. A secondary quality, such as heat or colour, is not, indeed, like the sensible effect, being a mode of a primary quality, such as motion ; but it is a distinct and specific variety of that primary quality ; it is the motion of a different kind of matter, it goes on independently of the sensible effect, and it is a knowable object of science. Thus, it has been discovered in natural philosophy that heat and lio-ht are not molar but molecular motions, that they o are motions of sether ; that they are, in rerum natura, different motions of different lengths, the waves of mere heat being longer than those of light, and that they are so disseminated throughout the universe as to produce no sensible effect incalculably oftener than they excite touch or vision. It was perceived by the genius of Bacon that heat is of two kinds, in or dine ad universum and in ordine ad sensum, the former being an insensible mode of corpus cular motion, the latter the same thing but with a rela tion such as -is competent to sense.1 The Atomists were too narrow in confining heat to the sensible effect of a distinct mode of matter in the external world, and Protagoras quite wrong in denying the distinctness of 1 Bacon, Nov. Org. ii. 20. CHAP. iv. ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 85 the external quality ; Bacon was right in regarding heat as a mode of motion in the external world, as well as a sensible quality in our senses. So with all other secondary qualities ; they are modes of primary qualities, but distinct modes ; they have a generic resemblance to other modes, but they have also specific differences. Sound is a vibration of air, heat and light undulations of rcther. The only plausible objection to this view would be that the names 'heat,' 'light,' and so on, should be confined to the sensible effects and not extended to their external causes. It must be confessed, also, that so long as distinctions of things are observed, the use of names is comparatively unimportant. But names are the vehicles of distinct ideas, and it is the duty of every science to have some distinct name for every real distinction of things. The specific modes of primary qualities must receive some name or other. It will not suffice to leave the external cause of sensible sound to the periphrasis, vibratory motion among the particles of an elastic aerial medium ; or that of light to the periphrasis, undulations in an ethereal medium per vading interstellar spaces and bodies formed of ponder able matter. New names might be invented, but they are not forthcoming, and it is doubtful whether they would be superior to, and still more doubtful whether they would be victorious over, the old names, ' sound ' and ' light.' Secondary qualities are real, though derivative, qualities of external objects, as well as qualities of sensible objects ; and their names should be equally extensive. In support of this view, let us quote a passage from Professor Stokes, ' On the Beneficial Effects of Li^ht,' all the more valuable because it was not 80 PHYSICAL REALISM PAKT i. written to support any general philosophy of secondary qualities :— ' Beyond both ends of the visible spectrum there lie radiations which do not affect the eye, but are never theless, as we have every reason to believe, of the same physical nature as those which do, from which they do not differ by any inherent quality. As the agent which excites vision has been called from time immemorial " light," or whatever may be the corresponding term in other languages, it will be convenient to use the same word to designate the agent considered in itself, and irrespectively of its capacity for exciting vision, a capacity which would be regarded as a mere accident of light, in the technical logical sense of that word. Accordingly I shall now use the word " light " to designate what, for want of a better term, I have just been calling "radiation," a word which would more properly denote the process of radiation than the thing radiated, be it the material or immaterial, be it matter or undulations ' (p. 6). Qualities, then, as distinguished by natural philo sophy, are divided as follows : — I. External, in or dine ad universum. 1. Primary, original qualities; e.g. duration, extension, motion. 2. Secondary, specific modes of primary quali ties ; e.g. sound, heat, light, as modes of motion. II. Internal, in or dine ad sensum. 1. Primary, and like external primary qualities, which cause them. 2. Secondary, unlike external secondary quali ties, which cause them. CHAP. iv. ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 87 It is to be noticed, in this division, that the derivative character of secondary qualities refers not to their sensible but to their external aspect. As sensible, we apprehend them in exactly the same way. Again, the ordinary man infers external qualities alike in both cases. The difference entirely arises when the scientific man begins to infer that external secondary are modes of primary qualities, because their sensible effects are so similar to those of primary qualities; for instance, the effects of external sound, heat and light are effects of motion by the laws of motion. To the Atomists is due, not only the foundation the theory of primary and secondary qualities, but also the discovery that the object of sense is not the external thin- itself, but an effect produced by the external thin on the senses. They supposed that effluxes, continual!; thrown off from bodies, come into contact with on oro-ans.1 They thus anticipated modern physical inquiry on the senses, although their necessary ignorance of the laws of motion prevented them from realising the vibra tions and undulations, which have taken the place oi emissions, in the case of hearing, sight, and the perception of temperature by touch. The consequence of this position to the theory of knowledge in Greek philosophy was that its immediate object was henceforward rally agreed to be not the thing at a distance, 1 result of the thing on the organs of sense. In the Atomistic theory the immediate object ^ c sense, though internal and representative, is neither im material nor psychical : it is a physical object, point has never been disproved. Modern physiology we have seen, has brought the motions of matter j i Arist. DC Divin. per Somn. 2 = 4G4 A G (Berlin cd.) ; cf. Pint. DC Plac. Phil iv. 8. 88 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. as the physical substances of the nerves ; but it has never shown that this physical object is converted into a psychical sensation, either at the extremities of the nerves, or in the nervous fibres, or in the nerve centres, or in the brain itself, or beyond it. Why, then, should we not perceive the physical effect in our internal organs ? The physical character of the immediate object of sensible knowledge was not at first forgotten. It sur vived in the Epicurean philosophy. It even left a relic in the philosophy of Plato, who always represents sensation as a motion communicated from matter through body to soul.1 Hence sense never appears in any Platonic dialogue as a part of the soul, nor the sensible object as something purely psychical. It is not in his theory of sense, but of reason, that Plato becomes idealistic. The objects of sense are, according to him, results of material motion communicated from body to soul ; the objects of rational knowledge are results com municated from immaterial ' forms ' to the pure soul. Aristotle was the author of a new theory of the sen sible object. He had an aversion to atomism, perhaps because he confused it with materialism. For atoms he substituted primary matter ; instead of figure, position, and arrangement, he regarded heat and cold, dry and liquid, as its primary contrarieties.2 The Atomists considered the external thing to be wholly corporeal ; Aristotle divided it into two heterogeneous substances — corporeal matter and incorporeal form 3 — the former of which was different for each individual, the latter the same for all individuals of one kind. While the Atomists had held that the sensible object which results from the 1 Plato, Phil 34 A ; Tim. 42 A, G4. 2 Arist. DC Gen. et Corr. ii. 1. 3 Id. Met. Z 7 = 1032 B 14. CHAP. iv. ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 89 external thing is a corporeal efllux, Aristotle persuaded himself and his followers that it is the identical incor poreal form transferred without the different corporeal matter from the external thing into the sensitive faculty, as an impression is transferred without the metal from a metallic seal into wax.1 For example, vision, accord ing to him, receives the essence of white without the matter of the external wax into the visual faculty. Hence his distinction of nutrition and sensation : in nutrition we receive the whole thing, in sense the form without the matter of the thing. He agreed, indeed, with his predecessors in the fundamental point that the external thing is not presented, but that the sensible object presented is a representative result of the external thing. But this object in our senses, which, according to the Atomists, was a corporeal efflux, was, according to Aristotle, an incorporeal form, called by himself ala-O^rov elSo?, and by his scholastic followers, species sensibilis. From his time onwards, the object of sense began to be usually regarded as not only internal, but also incorporeal, though not yet as a purely psychical object. Aristotle's new theory of the object and nature of sensitive perception is charged with errors. He substi tuted for the explanation of the world by particles, the abstractions of matter and form ; he inverted the real order of primary and secondary by making heat and cold original qualities ; he arbitrarily severed a single corporeal thing into a corporeal and an incorporeal half, and by this latter figment endeavoured to explain the object of sense. We see here the beginning of the false hypothesis that the object of sense is not a corporeal fact. Aristotle was right in thinking that sense does 1 Arist. De An. ii. 12. 90 PHYSICAL REALISM TART i. not perceive the external thing, wrong in thinking that what it perceives within is an incorporeal form. Hamilton has misunderstood these Aristotelian errors.1 He says truly enough that Aristotle distinguishes proper from common objects of sense,2 and that the former agree with the secondary, the latter with primary quali ties. 13 ut he misses the real point by supposing that Aristotle meant to derive the former from the latter. Aristotle distinguished proper and common sensibles solely in relation to the senses which perceive them. Heat and cold, for example, are proper sensible objects of touch ; but so far from being regarded by Aristotle as secondary qualities, they form one pair of his primary contrarieties of matter. The classification into common and proper is not intended by Aristotle for a classifica tion into primary and secondary ; so far from it, his primary qualities are falsely taken from what are really secondary qualities, heat and cold, dry and moist. Secondly, Hamilton rightly says that Aristotle calls such qualities as heat and cold affective qualities, be cause they produce affections in us.3 But we must not therefore infer that lie meant either that they produce this effect through insensible primary qualities, or that they are themselves mere affections in us, or that, being qualities outside, the affections are not like them. These are opinions of people who hold an atomistic theory of primary and secondary qualities, but they are not Aristotelian. In fact, the most fundamental defect in Aristotle's natural philosophy is the supposition that heat and cold are primary contrarieties of matter in capable of further resolution. His opinion was that 1 See Eeid's Works, ed. by Hamilton, Note D, on Primary and Secondary Qualities. 2 Arist. De An. ii. G. 3 Id. Cat. 8 = 9 A 28 seq. ORIGIN7 OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM (,H heat and cold are real and original qualities of matter, derived from no others, and that they produce in us affections of heat and cold similar to themselves. This, morever, was his theory of the perception of all qualities. Thirdly, Hamilton is right in saying that, according to Aristotle, there is an identity between the external object and the object perceived.1 But he is wrong in inferring from this identification that, according to Aristotle, the external object is presentatively perceived without any intermediate object. The identity is not of existence but of essence, not numerical but specific, not numero but specie. Aristotle supposed that in all members of a kind there is one form, and that, when one member of a kind produces another member, it pro pagates the form, or, as we say to this day in organisms, the species, from its own matter to the matter of the new recipient of the form or species. Thus he supposed man to beget man.2 Hence, in sensible knowledge, he supposed that the external object propagates the form of the sensible quality, such as heat, without its own matter into the matter of the sense, which thus receives the form or species of heat into its own matter without receiving the matter of the body which propagates the heat. Therefore the hot body and the hot affection of sense are the same only as the impression on the seal is the same as the impression on the wax, or as the father is the same as the son ; that is, the same in form or essence, not in matter or existence, the same specie but different numero, like but not the same objects. According to Aristotle, then, the sensible object is not numerically identical with the sensible object, but 1 Arist. De An. in. 2 = 425 B 25-7. 2 Id. Met. Z 7-8, esp. 1033 B 29-1034 A 8. 92 PHYSICAL REALISM PART i. only identical in essence. It is the form or species, without the matter of the external object,, propagated into the senses. Aristotle was no intuitive realist. He held, indeed, that sense perceives the identical essence of the external thing, but not the external thing itself; and he held that it receives this essence into the sensi tive faculty, and does not apprehend it in the external world. In short, his theory was a new form of repre sentation, in which the object of sense was regarded no longer as a corporeal efllux, but as an incorporeal essence received without the corporeal matter from a corporeal object into the senses, and there perceived. As the objects of sensible knowledge are sensible species, so the objects of rational knowledge are intel ligible species, according to Aristotle. The difference is in the mode of production. The former are propa gated by external objects into the sensitive faculty, the latter by active intelligence into passive intelligence. Aristotle has not explained this mysterious influence of intelligence on intelligence in the same soul ; nor is it O o probable that he proceeded on any other fact than the consciousness that, while we depend on externals to perceive, we can command our own thoughts. It would be, however, useless to go into this question. The important point for our present purpose is that both sensible and intelligible species are, in the view of Aristotle, immaterial, not material, objects. In his philo sophy, for the first time, we come to the view that all the immediate objects of knowledge are immaterial facts. We must not therefore fly to the supposition that Aristotle thought them to be psychical because they were immaterial. We have not yet exhausted the mys teries of the Aristotelian form. A form is supposed by him to be not only one in connection with many CHAP. iv. ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 93 matters of different members of the same kind, but also to be something different from matter, even when so closely conjoined with matter in fact, and so inseparable from it in definition, as concavity with nose in snubnose, and soul with body in an animal. Every form, the form of a triangle, the form of a stone, the form of a house, is an immaterial substance, even when conjoined with matter in a material substance. The form of God Him self is pure, not in the sense of being less material than other forms, but only in the sense of never being con joined with matter. Hence, sensible and intelligible species or forms are immaterial, not because they are in the soul, but simply because all forms are immaterial, according to Aristotle, who thought that if I per ceive a white paper, I receive from the paper into my sensitive faculty an identical essence of white, which was already incorporeal in the paper before it was com municated to the sensitive faculty of my soul. The object of sense, then, had, in his philosophy, ceased to be material, but had not yet become a psychical fact : it is an essence, which is not matter, whether it is without or within a soul. Descartes completed the separation of the sensible object from the external world. The Atomists had taken the first step by discovering that the object of sense is not the external thing, but an internal effect ; but they admitted that it is, like its external cause, purely physical, and no more has been proved to this very day. Aristotle, however, had proceeded to apply the hypothesis of incorporeal forms to sense, and sup posed that the object of sense is a sensible species, similar to the physical cause in identical incorporeal essence, but not in diverse corporeal matter. It remained for Descartes to take the final step and destroy the last 94 PHYSICAL REALISM TAUT i. vestige of resemblance to the physical cause by identi- O -L " J fying the object of sense with a psychical idea. The history of philosophy had insensibly led, or rather misled, Descartes into his ideal theory. In the philosophy of Aristotle the incorporeal is wider than the psychical, because all essences are incorporeal even in physical things. But in the interval between ancient and modern philosophy, the hypothesis of the incor- porealism of essences was discredited, partly by the attacks of Nominalism, but more successfully by the revival of natural philosophy, and especially by the return to Atomism, inaugurated by Bacon, from whom it passed to Descartes. Bacon discovered that the essence of anything physical is nothing but a uniform mode of its matter.1 Descartes thought that it is only a psychical idea.'2 In these circumstances his hypo thesis of the sensible object developed itself, as it were, from the course of history. The sensible object had been identified by Aristotle with the incorporeal essence ; the incorporeal had been recently expunged by Bacon from the physical world ; the essence was limited by Descartes himself to the psychical idea. What more natural than to regard the sensible object also as a psychical idea ? Descartes, it is true, went back to the Atomists for the analysis of nature into corpuscles. lie might also, especially since Galen's discoveries in the nervous system, have restored the Atomistic theory that the object of sense is a physical effect on our organs, and have added that it is an effect on the nervous system. His writings do, indeed, show that he was not always certain whether the sensible effect is physical or psy chical. Sometimes he even seems almost to express 1 Nov. Org. i. 51 ; ii. 17, 20, 52. 2 Princ. i. 58. CHAP. iv. ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 95 himself as if the idea itself were not distinct from the nervous imprint. But he finally and deliberately sepa rated it from the physical effect in the brain in his Replies to the Objections raised against his Medita tions. The ' Eesponsio ad Secundas Objectiones ' con tains a synthetic statement of reasons for the exist ence of God, arranged in geometrical order, and the second definition is a formal definition of the idea, as follows : — 6 By the name, Idea, I understand that form of any thought, by whose immediate perception I am conscious of that same thought ; so that I can express nothing in words in understanding that which I say, but that from this very fact it is certain there is in me an idea of that which is signified by those words. And so it is not only the images depicted in the fancy that I call ideas : nay, these I here by no means call ideas, so far as they are depicted in the corporeal fancy, that is, in some part of the brain, but only so far as they inform the mind itself turned towards that part of the brain.' The influence of Descartes did not at once make itself felt in all parts of philosophy. English natural philosophy in this as in other matters took an indepen dent course, which accounts for one finding Aristotle's theory of the sensible object surviving in Newton's Optics. In Quasst. 20 Newton asks : ' Aiinon sensoriuni animalium est locus cui substantia sentiens adest, et in quern sensibiles rerum species per nervos et cerebrum deferuntur, tit ibi prsesentes a prsesente sentiri possint ? ' Similarly English theology did not at first think it necessary to salvation to consider sensible objects, or sensation, or even consciousness itself, to be psy chical, as we may see from the following passage in 96 PHYSICAL REALISM TART I. 'Tritlieism charged upon Dr. Sherlock's new Notion of the Trinity,' by a Divine of the Church of Eno*- land l :- ' I deny that there is any such thing as sensation, whether internal or external, belonging to spirits not vitally united to organised bodies. For sensation is properly the perception of a sensible object by a sensible species of it imprinted upon and received into the proper organ by which each sensitive faculty operates and exerts itself. This, I say, is sensation, and accordingly, as it is external or internal, so it has external or internal organs allotted to it; but still both of them corporeal. And therefore for this man to talk of spiritual sensa tion is nonsense and a contradiction in the terms, and consequently not to be allowed' (p. 15). But mental philosophers, not only on the Continent but also in England, more quickly received the hypo thesis of a psychical object of sense. At first, Locke simply accepted the Cartesian ' idea.' Then Hume dis tinguished the ' impression ' from the idea. Kant made 6 phenomenon ' the fashionable term. Mill preferred ' sensation.' But all agree in some psychical object or other. Moreover, mental physiologists have passed over from Aristotle and Newton to Descartes, when they ought rather to have retraced their steps from Newton through Aristotle to the Atomists. The Cartesian hypo thesis, that the object of sense is a purely psychical idea, is not so near the truth as Aristotle's hypothesis, that it is an incorporeal but not psychical species in the sensitive faculty ; nor is the Aristotelian so near as the Atomistic hypothesis, that it is a purely physical effect on the bodily organs. All that is required to make this last, or rather this first, the truth is to substitute 1 Dr. South. CHAP. iv. ORIGIN OF PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM 97 for eilluxes mechanical motions, and for the bodily organs the nervous system sensibly affected. ' Meanwhile,' says Bacon, ' let nobody expect great progress in the sciences (especially on their productive side) unless natural philosophy has been extended to the special sciences, and the special sciences reduced to natural philosophy. Hence it happens that astronomy, optics, music, most of the mechanical arts, and (what may seem more strange) moral and political philosophy, and the logical sciences, have little or no extent in depth, but only slide over the surface and variety of things : because, as soon as those special sciences have been divided and established, they are no longer nourished by natural philosophy ; which, from the sources and true contemplations of the motions, rays, sounds, texture, and structure of bodies, affections, and intellectual apprehensions, had been able to impart to them new force and increase. It is not at all wonderful, if sciences do not grow, when they have been separated from their roots.' 1 The revival of Atomism by Bacon, together with the gradual establishment of the laws of motion in mechanics, from Galileo to Newton, produced an instauration of natural philosophy. Let us now, in the same spirit, return to natural philosophy, in order to restore mental philosophy. ' Iiiteritus rei arcetur per reductionem ejus ad principia.' 1 Bacon, Nov. Org. i. 80. H PART II. PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM. ' Pcssimwni cnim omnium cst aiigurium quod ex Conscnsu capitur in rclus IntcllcctualiltusS BACON, Kov. Org. i. 77. H 2 101 CHAPTEE V. DESCARTES. PHILOSOPHY ought to begin in doubt. But I cannot doubt that I think. Cogito, ergo sum. As a thinking I being, I am a soul, distinct from the body. Soul is ; thinking substance; body is extended substance; they ; are heterogeneous to each other. The soul immediately apprehends ideas, innate, adventitious, and fictitious. The clearness and distinctness of ideas are a criterion of truth, and by the veracity of God, enable me to know objects beyond ideas. Starting from ideas, I infer a physical world of bodies and insensible corpuscles, whose qualities are partly like and partly unlike those which I perceive as sensible ideas, and whose insensible modes produce sensible ideas. These are the cardinal points of Cartesian idealism. Cogito, ergo sum. — I think, therefore I am. This is the indubitable fact, which Descartes had the undying! merit of elevating into a principle in mental philosophy.) The proposition was not new. Aristotle asserted our consciousness of our operations,1 and even recognised this fact as a proof of our existence. But he did not convert the proposition into a psychological principle. He rightly founded the distinctions of operations on the distinctions of their objects: hence his discovery of nearly all that is known in mental philosophy. He 1 Eth. Nic. ix. 9, 9. 102 PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM PART n. wrongly neglected the consciousness of the operations about those objects : hence his tendency to dogmatism. Descartes supplied a defect in psychology when he discovered the necessity of using as a principle the con- jsciousness which says to each of us: 'I think; that is, I feel, perceive, remember, imagine, judge, reason, ^ desire, will : I therefore am.' It is a principle. Is it the only principle of psycho logy ? How far will this conscious fact, that I am, carry me ? I am conscious that I am a thinking subject. But two further questions immediately present them-, selves : what am I, and what do I apprehend ? What is the thinking subject, and what the apprehended ob ject? Now the mere consciousness that I think will vnot of itself solve the nature of either subject or object. The new principle of thinking was no more fitted than the old principle of contradiction to be a universal source of all philosophy : it must be accepted, without pledging us to all the Cartesian deductions. What" is the thinking subject? What am I? This terrific question is answered by Descartes, as if it im mediately followed from the principle, I think therefore I am, but really by another argument. He cannot say, I am conscious that I now think, as soul, without a body. He therefore substitutes the hypothesis, I can suppose that I had no body and was still thinking. He then concludes that I, as thinking subject, am not body but soul. Thus, by an easy transition, he leads his readers from thinking subject to soul, and makes, not the original principle, but an hypothesis and a problem atic conclusion the real premises of his philosophy. In order that we may feel the weakness of this non sequitur, let us quote from the ' Discussion on Method,' Part IV., the passage which immediately follows the CHAP. v. DESCARTES 103 enunciation of the principle, I think therefore I am : — - ' In the next place, I attentively examined what I was, and as I observed that I could suppose that I had no body, and that there was no world nor any place in which I might be ; but that I could not therefore sup pose that I was not ; and that, on the contrary, from the very circumstance that I thought to doubt of the truth of other things, it most clearly and certainly fol lowed that I was ; while, on the other hand, if I had only ceased to think, although all the other objects which I had ever imagined had been in reality existent, I would have had no reason to believe that I existed ; I thence concluded that I was a substance whose whole essence or nature consists only in thinking, and which, that it may exist, has need of no place, nor is dependent on any material thing ; so that " I," that is to say, the mind by which I am what I am, is plainly distinct from j the body, and is even more easily known than the latter, and is such, that although the latter were not, it would still continue to be all that it is.' ' I could suppose I had no body.' What is the nature of this proposition ? It is an hypothesis of what j might be but is not. I am not conscious that I have no / body ; I am at best only conscious of the supposition, which does not become any less a supposition through my being conscious of making it. Nor is it deduced from the consciousness that I think, but is a separate hypothesis. Again, how do we get to the proposition, ; I am a thinking substance wholly distinct from the body ? It is a conclusion not from the original principle alone, but also from the subsequent hypothesis, requiring also a second hypothesis, that without a body I should still be thinking. 104 PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM PART IT. We must, therefore, most carefully distinguish the original principle, cogito, ergo sum, from the subsequent conclusion, I am a soul. In the first place, I am con- £cious of the former, not of the latter. I am conscious 'that I am a thinking subject : I am not conscious that jthis thinking subject is not body but soul. Secondly, in order to deduce the conclusion, the principle requires the intervention of two hypotheses — that I could have no body and that I should still be thinking ; and in both / cases I am conscious of making the suppositions, but \ not conscious of the facts that I have no body and am 1 still thinking. But sectetur partem conclusio deteriorem. An hypothetical premise produces an hypothetical con clusion. The conclusion, then, that the thinking subject is not body but soul, has not the certainty of the rinciple, coqito, ergo sum, but is vitiated by the hypo- heses coy w^fh ^ Thus does Descartes lead his i reader to confuse the thinker and the soul, and transfer tHe conscious certainty of being res coqitans to the hypo thesiiTof being res a corpore plane distincta. "That T am a thinking subject is a fact of conscious ness ; but what I am, as thinking subject, is a matter of argument. There are three possible alternatives : Jiie ^body, the_soul, the man. Nor can we decide between these three alternatives by consciousness alone. Con sciousness, without hypothesis, never made a philoso pher either a materialist or a spiritualist. We must not make a fetish of consciousness, but interrogate it carefully, remember its superficiality, add to it observa tion, and combine both with reasoning. In discussions of this kind a false issue is generally raised at once by speaking of the consciousness of thoughts. This is an abstraction, useful indeed f°r some purposes, but still an abstraction, or rather a CHAP. V. DESCARTES 105 double abstraction. There is no such a thing as con sciousness, and no such a thing as a thought ;_ I am conscious, and I am conscious that 1 think. Conscious ness and thought are not there, waiting for a subject ; they already have a subject, or rather subjects — myself, yourself, every other thinker. Descartes, in a great measure at all events, avoided this fallacy of hypostasis- ing abstractions. He was aware that there is no con sciousness of thoughts, but I am conscious that I think. He surreptitiously changed the thinker into soul, but not into abstract thoughts. Those modern philosophers who suppose consciousness of thoughts are not votaries of consciousness, but victims of abstraction. I am, then, not thoughts, but a thinker or thinking subject. But what is this subject which thinks ? What part of me is the factor, or what parts are the factors of thinking ? In this mortal state, in which I cannot ap prehend myself without my body, I am not conscious that I think without my body. Nay, I am conscious that I think with my body. Whatever operation I take, I in variably find that I am conscious, not of the operation, which I may afterwards abstract, but of myself per- j forming it ; I am not conscious that I perform it by my • soul without my body, because, though I am conscious,' that I am a thinking subject, I am not conscious that) this is a soul ; nor am I conscious that I do it by my body without my soul, for reasons to follow presently. I am conscious that I perform every operation by my body, partly, somehow, and somewhere. I consciously feel pleased and pained in various parts of my body. I * cannot disengage my consciousness of toothache from / my mouth, or of headache from my head. LjLHL_coj}- scious of using my bodily senses in touch, taste, vision, hearing, and smell. I do not Consciously first feel the 106 PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM PART IT. sensation and then refer it to the bodily member ; I am not conscious of these two steps. Seasoning is the highest kind of thinking ; I am conscious of doing it , in my head, and by no force of abstraction can I get it t«»»wJout °f mJ bead. Similarly I am conscious that I will ^ ^ in my head, and I am conscious that my head may ache with reasoning, and deliberating, and resolving. My (body is not a mere companion but a conscjou.fi pnrf.npr °f all jny thoughts. Bui consciousness is a superficial power. "In speak ing of the data of sense I remarked that by an illusion, arising from the confusion of sense and inference, we ^cannot help seeming to be conscious that sense per- jpeives an external object, though we can make ourselves independent of the illusion by science, which dis- jtinguishes the external from the sensible. There is a similar illusion about our consciousness of the thinking subject, and fortunately we can explain it and conquer it by science. The illusion is that we perform some of our operations on the surfaces by the superficial mem bers of our bodies. The causes of the illusion are that we often observe the outer surfaces of our bodies when we are performing an internal operation, and we are at the same time unconscious of the inner structures and ] motions of our nerves and brain. The way to make | ourselves conquer the illusion is by the study of science, j which shows that what performs the operation is not I the outer surface but the inner nervous system. For example, we are conscious that we see something red somehow by our bodily organs of sight. Now, though we are sensible of the optic nerve so far as it is sensibly affected with red, we are neither sensible nor conscious of it as nervously constituted. But from very early infancy we observe, i.e. directly infer from sensation, CHAP. V. DESCARTES 107 the surfaces of our bodies. By putting our hands on our eyes we find that they no longer see red, and we infer that it was our eyes that saw red. It is so with all our external senses, as they are called from this illusion of observation. Not consciousness, but obser vation from very early infancy, made us believe that it was the periphery that is sensitive. But the inference became automatic before we were attentively conscious, and we cannot help seeming to be conscious that our eyes see. Eeally, however, as science discovers at last, the eyes are but avenues to vision, and wliaLsees is not Qur_eyes but the optic nerve in connection with the brain. A more complicated instance is when a person who has lost a limb believes that the pain, which he really feels in the nerves, is still in the limb. His con sciousness told him but vaguely where he feels the pain, his observations connected it with the surface of the limb; hence the illusion. Science alone can conquer such illusions of observation. The rough-and-ready way of dealing with this evi dence is to draw the further inference that we do not localise any operation except by observation and ana tomy, and that consciousness has nothing to do with the body. But this inference goes far beyond the facts. Observation is limited to the surface of the body, but the operations, of which we are conscious, are not. Now, even when they are purely internal, we are still conscious that they are somehow performed by the body, without observation and before science. For example, we are conscious of the pangs of hunger in the region of the stomach, to descend to the depths of consciousness : to rise to its summit, we are conscious of the process of reasoning in the region of the head. But in neither case does observation of the surface of 108 PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM TART n. the body reveal the whereabouts of the operation : yet we are conscious of the body performing it, without waiting for science. But there is another defect, for which the conscious ness of the body as a factor in thinking is responsible. lit tells me very indefinitely what part is engaged in a [particular operation. The cause of this indefiniteness ;is the unconsciousness of nervous structure and motion. The correction of it is the science of nervous structure and motion. Thus, confining ourselves entirely to in ternal operations, the locality of which is not accessible j to external observation, I am conscious of the pain of I hunger somewhere in the region of the stomach ; sciejq.ce \reduces this indefinite verdict to definiteness by proving jthe connection of the nerves of that region with the /brain. Consciousness again says indefinitely, 'I think in my head ' ; science tells me, ' Yes, in your brain.' Here science only corrects consciousness : it does not contradict it. Consciousness apprehends the indefinite region at work, science discovers the definite nervous structure in the direction of that region. Secondly, unless consciousness apprehended the region, science could not assign the nervous structure ; if we were not I already conscious of reasoning in the head, anatomy 1 would not convince us that we reason in the brain. Thirdly, sometimes consciousness apprehends the region without science having yet discovered the nervous structure ; for example, we are conscious, in what is inadequately called muscular sense, not indeed of mus cular motion but of the action of our limbs, though but vaguely and indefinitely ; but on this occasion science is still more vague and indefinite, having dis covered the nervous mechanism of muscular motion, but not of muscular sense. Finally, however wrong CHAP. V. DESCATITES 109 consciousness may be in the definite locality of a parti cular operation, science never disproves that we are conscious of its being performed somewhere in the body. I am conscious that I perform all my operations somehow or another, partly by the body, with more or less definiteness ; science discovers the definite locality, still within the body. There are two points, which sometimes appear in biological treatises, but are not proved. In the first place, as we have already seen, there is no biological > proof that cerebral motion is transmuted into a psy chical sensation. Secondly, biologists often distinguish a sensation from its localisation ; at the same time they sometimes confuse its localisation in the body with the inference of its external cause. There is a great differ-j ence between a sensation of an internal sensible object and the inference of its external cause, as we hav3 already seen in this essay. But there is no difference between the sensation and its internal localisation in the sentient subject ; there is no proof of these two steps. I am conscious of the sensation in a locality of my body. Neither consciousness nor science proves that I first have a sensation, then localise it in my body, and, thirdly, infer its external cause. They prove together that I first have a sensation located in some part of my body, and then infer the external causa; which produces it. There is another point, which is proved in biology, but does not disprove the consciousness of the body as a factor in thinking. I refer to subjective sensations. |/ We have sensations similar to our ordinary sensations, but not produced by the ordinary external cause. Thus, i a prize-fighter may be made by a blow to see stars ; a drunkard under the influence of delirium tremens may 110 PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM PART ir. : have a vision of tlie devil. Such sensations are excel- ent instances to sliow that the sensible object is different from the external original, and is not always caused by it ; that there are internal causes of sensations in the / nerves ; and that the superficial structure of the eye is \ a cause, not a subject, of vision. But they do not show jthat the soul is the sole subject of vision. A prize fighter seeing stars, a drunkard's vision of the devil, are odd proofs of psychical sensations. The term ' sub jective' sensations is misleading, because, in the recent sense of the word, it suggests 'psychical,' without proving it. There is no evidence that sensation, or any other | operation, is purely psychical. There is evidence that Jthe body is a factor in all thinking. It is the evidence of consciousness, interpreted by science. I am not conscious first of a sensation, and then of its locali- \sation. I am conscious that I feel, perceive, reason, / will, partly by my bod}? . External observation connects some of these operations with the surface of the body. Science shows that I do all of them by my nervous system. Science dispels the illusion of observation, and corrects the indefiniteness of consciousness. Science further traces the continuity of the nervous system, and leaves no gap for purely psychical operations, . Xow, \ ordinary and scientific observation being limited to the jbody, if I were only conscious of mere thinking, I should know my body only as an unthinking cause. But when I cannot be conscious that I perform any operation Without being conscious that I perform it somehow in /my body, that I feel headache, that I use my bodily senses to see, touch, hear, and so on, and that I reason \in my head, scientific observation becomes an inter preter of my consciousness that I use my body to think, CHAP. v. DESCARTES HI and shows that the part which I use is the brain in con nection with the nervous system. The body is a patent factor of the thinking subject. The neglect of it is the fallacy of spiritualism. It does not follow that the body is the sole factor of thinking. Man does not know the whole of himself, either by consciousness or by scientific observation ; the former is superficial, the latter limited. I am conscious/ that I perform my operations partly by my body : science observes the nervous system, and in combination with! consciousness, infers that the nervous system is that by which the body in part performs these operations. But I am not conscious that my body, nor does science observe that the nervous system, is the whole thinking subject. There is no operation which can be traced throughout its whole course. I am conscious that I use my bodily senses in sensation and my head in reasoning. Science observes the nervous system and brain. But it has not solved the problem of nervous and cerebral motion. If it solved that problem, it would still remain to prove that nervous motion is completely identical writh the operation of which I am conscious. It is partly so, because I am conscious of partly per forming the operation by the body, in which science ob serves the nervous system and the motion it performs during the operation. . But it is another thing to prove that the conscious operation and the nervous motion are completely identical, because I am conscious of the operation without observing it, and science observes the motion without being conscious of it. This differ ence of evidence does not, indeed, prove a complete difference, because nervous motion and conscious opera tion may be the same fact approached from different sides, but the very difference of evidence makes it dim- 112 PSYCHOLOGICAL IDEALISM PART n. cult to prove a complete identity of fact. Another evidence might be evoked — the method of explanation. If all the facts of conscious operations were known, and nervous motions were known, it might be urged that the former are explicable by the latter, as the facts of light are explicable by undulating motion. But there is a great difference in the two cases. In the case of li